We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Two scientists more than anyone else have contributed in defining our understanding of gravity: Newton in 1679 and Einstein in 1915. The mathematical frameworks the two have developed and proposed, however, are very different. Newton’s gravity is the one we learn at school and is normally taught at university. It provides a very natural interpretation of what we experience - the apple falls from the tree because the Earth attracts it! Einstein’s gravity is studied only in the most advanced courses at the university and provides a very counterintuitive explanation, requiring the concepts of spacetime and curvature. This chapter will provide a first description of the Einstein equations and, although it will not enter into the mathematical aspects of the equations, it will explain the basic concepts behind them. Acquiring a first qualitative understanding of Einstein equations will be useful to comprehend better the concept of spacetime curvature discussed in Chapter 4.
Famously, Klein and Einstein were embroiled in an epistolary dispute over whether General Relativity has any physically meaningful conserved quantities. This chapter explores the consequences of Noether’s second theorem for this debate and connects it to Einstein’s search for a ‘substantive’ version of general covariance as well as his quest to extend the Principle of Relativity. The chapter’s argument is that Noether’s second theorem provides a clear way to distinguish between theories in which gauge or diffeomorphism symmetry is doing real work in defining charges, as opposed to cases in which this symmetry stems from Kretchmannization. Finally, a comment is made on the relationship between this Noetherian form of substantive general covariance and the notion of ‘background independence’.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.