Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-ks5gx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-19T00:25:49.498Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - The Empirical Component of Analytic Jurisprudence

from Part I - Foundations and Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2025

Kevin Tobia
Affiliation:
Georgetown University, Washington DC
Get access

Summary

As a branch of analytic philosophy, jurisprudence, understood as legal philosophy, is often thought to be a nonempirical enterprise. It turns out, however, that unresearched, unsupported, and largely impressionistic empirical assertions have long been a part of the analytic jurisprudential enterprise. Recognizing this is the first step towards examining and testing these empirical assertions. Using the proclivity of ordinary people to obey the law (or not) because of the content-independent existence of law as one example of such an assertion, this chapter explores how that assumption might be tested by experimental and other means, as a prolegomenon to testing the empirical claims and assumptions that have long pervaded even the most traditional jurisprudence.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Austin, J. L.A Plea for Excuses.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57 (1957): 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Rumble, Wilfrid E. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996 (1839).Google Scholar
Batson, Daniel C., & Shaw, Laura L.. “Evidence for Altruism: Toward a Pluralism of Prosocial Motives.Psychological Inquiry 1 (1991): 107–22.Google Scholar
Booth, Wayne C. The Rhetoric of Fiction. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1961 (republished 1991).Google Scholar
Clarke, Ronald V., Contre, Stephan, & Petrossian, Gohar. “Deterrence and Fare Evasion: Results of a Natural Experiment.Security Journal 23 (2010): 5–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, Jules L. The Practice of Principle: In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Cope, Kevin L. “Experimental Studies on the Normative Force of Law.” University of Virginia Public Law and Legal Theory Paper Series 2023–45, available at SSRN, abstract=4456250 (May 2023).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Del Mar, Maksymilian (ed.). Legal Theory and the Social Sciences. London: Routledge, 2017.Google Scholar
Dickson, Julie. Evaluation and Legal Theory. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2001.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, Brendan. “Legal Positivism and the Philosophy of Language: A Critique of H. L. A. Hart’s ‘Descriptive Sociology.’Legal Studies 6 (1986): 115–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilovich, Thomas. How We Know What Isn’t So: The Fallibility of Human Reason in Everyday Life. New York: Free Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. The Concept of Law. Bulloch, Penelope, Raz, Joseph, and Green, Leslie (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3rd ed., 2012 (1961).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A.Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons.” In Hart, H. L. A. (ed.). Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982, 243–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A.The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 49 (1948–49): 171–94.Google Scholar
Himma, Kenneth Einar. Coercion and the Nature of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Himma, Kenneth Einar. “The Authorization of Coercive Enforcement Mechanisms as a Conceptually Necessary Feature of Law.Jurisprudence 7 (2016): 593–626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Himma, Kenneth Einar. “H. L. A. Hart and the Practical Difference Thesis.Legal Theory 9 (2003): 1–43.Google Scholar
Holmes, Oliver Wendell, Jr. “The Path of the Law.Harvard Law Review 10 (1897): 457–78.Google Scholar
King, Gary, Keohane, Robert O., & Verba, Sidney. Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krygier, Martin. “The Concept of Law and Social Theory.Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 2 (1982): 155–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacey, Nicola. “The Path Not Taken: H. L. A. Hart’s Essay on Discretion.Harvard Law Review 127 (2013): 636–51.Google Scholar
Lacey, Nicola. A Life of H. L. A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.Google Scholar
Leiter, Brian. “The Demarcation Problem in Jurisprudence: A New Case for Skepticism.Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31 (2011): 663–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. H. L. A. Hart. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2nd ed., 2008.Google Scholar
Marmor, Andrei. Interpretation and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd ed., 2005.Google Scholar
Penner, Louis A.Prosocial Behavior: Multilevel Perspectives.Annual Review of Psychology 56 (2005): 365–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Piliavin, Jane Allyn, & Charng, Hong-Wen. “Altruism: A Review of Recent Theory and Research.American Review of Sociology 16 (1990): 27–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plaxton, Michael. “The Challenge of the Puzzled Man.McGill Law Journal 58 (2012): 451–80.Google Scholar
Plunkett, David, & Shapiro, Scott. “Law, Morality, and Everything Else: General Jurisprudence as a Branch of Metanormative Inquiry.Ethics 128 (2017): 37–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. “Can There Be a Theory of Law?” In Golding, Martin P., & Edmundson, William A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2005, 324–42.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. “On the Nature of Law.Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 82 (1996): 1–25.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, Donald H.Reasons, Authority, and the Meaning of ‘Obey’: Further Thoughts on Raz and Obedience to Law.Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 3 (1990): 3–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, Frederick. The Force of Law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Schauer, Frederick. “Was Austin Right After All?Ratio Juris 23 (2010): 10–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, Frederick. “A Comment on the Structure of Rights.Georgia Law Review 21 (1993): 415–34.Google Scholar
Schelling, Thomas. Micromotives and Macrobehavior. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1978.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Scott J. Legality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spamann, Holger, & Klöhn, Lars. “Can Law Students Replace Judges in Experiments of Judicial Decision-Making?” Harvard Law School Public Law Working Paper 1093 (May 15, 2023), available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=4362199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spamann, Holger, & Klöhn, Lars. “Justice Is Less Blind, and Less Legalistic, than We Thought: Evidence from an Experiment with Real Judges.Journal of Legal Studies 45 (2016): 255–80.Google Scholar
Sugarman, David. “Hart Interviewed: H. L. A. Hart in Conversation with David Sugarman.Journal of Law and Society 32 (2005): 267–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tur, R. H. S.What Is Jurisprudence?Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1978): 149–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Twining, William. “Schauer on Hart.Harvard Law Review Forum 119 (2006): 122–30.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom R.Understanding the Force of Law.Tulsa Law Review 51 (2016): 507–19.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom R. Why People Obey the Law. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2nd ed., 2006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tyler, Tom R.Beyond Self-Interest: Why People Obey Laws and Accept Judicial Decisions.The Responsive Community 8(4) (Fall 1998): 44–52.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom R.Compliance with Intellectual Property Laws: A Psychological Perspective.NYU Journal of International Law and Politics 29 (1997): 213–26.Google Scholar
Wistrich, Andrew J., Rachlinski, Jeffrey J., & Guthrie, Chris. “‘Heart versus Head’ Do Judges Follow the Law or Follow Their Feelings?Texas Law Review 93 (2014): 855–923.Google Scholar
Wistrich, Andrew J., Rachlinski, Jeffrey J., & Guthrie, Chris. “Can Judges Ignore Inadmissible Information? The Difficulty of Deliberately Disregarding.University of Pennsylvania Law Review 153 (2005): 1251–1345.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×