Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-cp4x8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-23T10:07:59.360Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Rules

from Part II - Introductions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2025

Kevin Tobia
Affiliation:
Georgetown University, Washington DC
Get access

Summary

Rules are ubiquitous. They figure prominently in all kinds of practical reasoning. Rules are especially important in jurisprudence, occupying a central role in answers to the question of “what is law?” In this chapter, we start by reviewing the evidence showing that both textual and extratextual elements exert influence over rule violation judgments (Section II). Most studies about rules contrast text with an extratextual element identified as the “purpose” or “spirit” of the rule. But what counts as the purpose or the spirit of a rule? Is it the goal intended by the rule maker? Or is purpose necessarily moral? Section III reviews the results of experiments designed to answer these questions. These studies show that the extratextual element that’s relevant for the folk concept of rule is moral in nature. Section IV turns to the different explanations that have been entertained in the literature for the pattern of results described in Sections II and III. Finally, in Section V we discuss some other extratextual elements that have been investigated in the literature. We conclude with a brief discussion of future directions.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Alexander, L. & Sherwin, E. (2001). The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of Law. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Alexander, L. & Sherwin, E. (2008). Demystifying Legal Reasoning. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Almeida, G. F. C. F. (2024). A Dual Character Theory of Law. Journal of Legal Philosophy, 49(1), 1–24. https://doi.org/10.4337/jlp.2024.01.01CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Almeida, G. F. C. F., Knobe, J., Struchiner, N., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2022). Purposes in Law and in Life: An Experimental Investigation of Purpose Attribution. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 36(1), 1–36. https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2022.20Google Scholar
Almeida, G. F. C. F., Struchiner, N., & Hannikainen, I. (2023a). Rule Is a Dual Character Concept. Cognition, 230, 105259. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2022.105259Google Scholar
Almeida, G. F. C. F., Struchiner, N., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2023b). The Experimental Jurisprudence of the Concept of Rule: Implications for the Hart-Fuller Debate. In Prochownik, K. M. & Magen, S. (Eds.), Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Law. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Atiq, E. (2020). There Are No Easy Counterexamples to Legal Anti-positivism. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 17(1). https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v17i1.701Google Scholar
Bregant, J., Wellbery, I., & Shaw, A. (2019). Crime but Not Punishment? Children Are More Lenient toward Rule-Breaking When the “Spirit of the Law” Is Unbroken. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 178, 266–282. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jecp.2018.09.019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R. (2001). Taking Rights Seriously. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Engelmann, N., Hannikainen, I. R., González-García, C., & Ruz, M. (2024). Understanding Rule Enforcement Using Drift Diffusion Models. In Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (Vol. 46).Google Scholar
Flanagan, B., Almeida, G. F. C. F., Struchiner, N., & Hannikainen, I. (2023). Moral Appraisals Guide Intuitive Legal Determinations. Law and Human Behavior, 47(2), 367–383. https://doi.org/10.1037/lhb0000527CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Flanagan, B. & Hannikainen, I. R. (2022). The Folk Concept of Law: Law Is Intrinsically Moral. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 100(1), 165–179. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2020.1833953CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, L. L. (1969). The Morality of Law. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Garcia, S. M., Chen, P., & Gordon, M. T. (2014). The Letter versus the Spirit of the Law: A Lay Perspective on Culpability. Judgment and Decision Making, 9(5), 479–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hannikainen, I., Tobia, K., Almeida, G. F. C. F., Struchiner, N., Kneer, M., Bystranowski, P., Dranseika, V., Strohmaier, N., Bensinger, S., Dolinina, K., Janik, B., Lauraityte, E., Laakasuo, M., Liefgreen, A., Neiders, I., Próchnicki, M., Rosas Martinez, A., Sundvall, J., & Zuradzki, T. (2022). Coordination and Expertise Foster Legal Textualism. PNAS, 119(44). https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2206531119CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hart, H. (1994). The Concept of Law (2nd edition). Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1983). Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253884.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LaCosse, J. & Quintanilla, V. (2021). Empathy Influences the Interpretation of Whether Others Have Violated Everyday Indeterminate Rules. Law and Human Behavior, 45(4), 287–309. https://doi.org/10.1037/lhb0000456CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leiter, B. (2020). Critical Remarks on Shapiro’s Legality and the “Grounding Turn” in Recent Jurisprudence. SSRN Electronic Journal. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3700513CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, S., Kleiman-Weiner, M., Chater, N., Cushman, F. A., & Tenenbaum, J. (2022). When Rules Are Over-Ruled: Virtual Bargaining as a Contractualist Method of Moral Judgment. Cognition, 250, 105790. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/k5pu8Google Scholar
Liao, S., Meskin, A., & Knobe, J. (2020). Dual Character Art Concepts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 101(1), 102–128. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12301CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miotto, L. (2021). What Makes Law Coercive When It Is Coercive. Archiv fuer Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 107(2), 235. https://doi.org/10.25162/arsp-2021-0013Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (2021). Rational Rules: Towards a Theory of Moral Learning. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reuter, K. (2019). Dual Character Concepts. Philosophy Compass, 14(1), e125571. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, F. (2002). Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. (2008). A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park. New York University Law Review, 83(4), 1109–1134.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. (2009). Thinking Like a Lawyer: A New Introduction to Legal Reasoning. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, F. (2015). The Force of Law. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Struchiner, N., Almeida, G. F. C. F., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2020). Legal Decision-Making and the Abstract/Concrete Paradox. Cognition, 205, 104421. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104421CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Struchiner, N., Hannikainen, I. R., & Almeida, G. F. C. F. (2020). An Experimental Guide to Vehicles in the Park. Judgment and Decision Making, 15(3), 312–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tobia, K. P. (2020). Testing Ordinary Meaning. Harvard Law Review, 134(2), 726–806.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2019). Excuse Validation: A Cross‐Cultural Study. Cognitive Science, 43(8), e12748. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12748CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turri, J. & Blouw, P. (2015). Excuse Validation: A Study in Rule-Breaking. Philosophical Studies, 172(3), 615–634. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0322-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vega Gomez, J. (2014). The Hart-Fuller Debate. Philosophy Compass, 9(1), 45–53. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12096Google Scholar
Wylie, J. & Gantman, A. P. (2023). Doesn’t Everybody Jaywalk? On Codified Rules That Are Seldom Followed and Selectively Punished. Cognition, 231, 105323. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2022.105323CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×