Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-g4j75 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-04T01:02:03.888Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 January 2025

Tyler Huismann
Affiliation:
University of Oklahoma
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Brunschwig, J. (2007) Aristote: Topiques Livres V–VIII. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Rashed, M. (2005) Aristote: De la génération et de la corruption. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1924) Aristotle’s Metaphysics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1936) Aristotle’s Physics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1949) Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1958) Aristotelis Topica et Sophistici elenchi. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1961) Aristotlis De anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas Aquinas. (1971) In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio. Ed. Cathala, M. R. and Spiazzi, R. M.. Rome: Marietti.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Ackrill, J. (1963) Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1976a) Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Books M and N. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1984) The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Vol. 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1993) Aristotle: Posterior Analytics. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. (2003) Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Ζ and Η. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Charlton, W. (1970) Aristotle: Physics I and II. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hussey, E. (1993) Aristotle: Physics III and IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
John, B. (2001) Summulae de dialectica. Trans. Klima, G.. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
John, P. (1999) On Aristotle’s on Coming to Be and Perishing 1.1–5. Trans. Williams, C. J. F.. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kirwan, C. (1993) Aristotle: Metaphysics Γ, Δ, and Ε. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Makin, S. (2006) Aristotle: Metaphysics Book Θ. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pickard-Cambridge, W. A. (1984) “Topics.” In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Vol. 1, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Platt, A. (1984) Generation of Animals. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Vol. 1, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. (2016) Aristotle: Metaphysics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. (2018) Aristotle: Physics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Relihan, J. (2001) Boethius: Consolation of Philosophy. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (2009) Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics. Rev. L. Brown. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Simplicius, (1997) On Aristotle: Physics 2. Trans. Fleet, Barrie. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Smith, R. (1997) Aristotle: Topics, Books I and VIII. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Striker, G. (2009) Aristotle: Prior Analytics: Books 1 and 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Themistius, (2012) On Aristotle: Physics 1–3. Trans. Todd, R.. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Waterfield, R. (2008) Aristotle: Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, C. J. F. (1982) Aristotle’s De generatione et corruptione. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackrill, J. L. (1978) “Aristotle on Action.” Mind, Vol. 87, No. 4, 595-601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, J. (2015) “Aristotle on Chance as an Accidental Cause.” In Aristotle’s Physics: A Critical Guide, ed. Leunissen, M.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Allison, J. (1981) “ΠΑΡΑΣΚΕΥΗ: Process-Product Ambiguity in Thucydides VI.” Hermes, Vol. 109, No. 1, 118-123.Google Scholar
Ando, T. (1974) Metaphysics: A Critical Survey of Its Meaning. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1976b) “Davidson and Anscombe on ‘The Same Action.’Mind, Vol. 85, No. 338, 251-257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1982) “Aristotle on Inefficient Causes.” The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 32, No. 129, 311-326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958) “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy, Vol. 33, No. 124, 1-19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963) Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1969) “Causality and Extensionality.” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 66, No. 6, 152-159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1979) “Under a Description.” Noûs, Vol. 13, No. 2, 219-233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. and Geach, P. T. (1961) Three Philosophers. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, P. (2013) “Causation, Coincidence, and Commensuration.” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 162, No. 2, 447-464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bäck, A. (1991) On Reduplication: Logical Theories of Qualification. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bäck, A. (2014) Aristotle’s Theory of Abstraction. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, S. (2021) “Aristotle on the Nature and Politics of Medicine.” Apeiron, Vol. 54, No. 4, 411-449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bailey, D. T. J. (2014) “Platonic Causes Revisited.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 52, No. 1, 15-32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1939) “Greek Science and Mechanism: I. Aristotle on Nature and Chance.” Classical Quarterly, Vol. 33, No. 3/4, 129-138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J. (1984) The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Vol. 2. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J.. (2008) “What, Even Bedbugs? Review: Creationism and Its Critics.” London Review of Books, Vol. 30, No. 11.Google Scholar
Barnes, J.. (2012a) “Property in Aristotle’s Topics.” In Logical Matters, ed. Bonelli, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J.. (2012b) “Grammar on Aristotle’s terms.” In Logical Matters, ed. Bonelli, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J.. (2012c) “Logical Form and Logical Matter.” In Logical Matters, ed. Bonelli, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bechler, Z. (1995) Aristotle’s Theory of Actuality. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. (1994) “The ‘Namely’ Analysis of the ‘By’-locution.” Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 17, No. 1, 29-51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, R. (1998) “Plato’s Discovery of Metaphysics: The New Methodos of the Phaedo.” In Method in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Gentzler, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. (2012) “Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bowin, J. (2008) “Aristotle on Identity and Persistence.” Apeiron, Vol. 41, No. 1, 63-88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. (1993) “Aristotle’s Perceptual Realism.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 31, Supplement, 137-159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. (2009) “Nicomachean Ethics, VII.8-9 (1151b22): Akrasia, enkrateia, and Look-Alikes.” In Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Book VII Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchheim, T. (2007) “Effective Primary Causes: The Notion of Contact and the Possibility of Acting without Being Affected in Aristotle’s De Generatione et Corruptione.” In Reading Ancient Texts, Vol. 2, ed. Stern-Gillet, S. and Corrigan, K.. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Buller, D. J. (1999) “Introduction,” In Function, Selection, and Design, ed. Bullder, D. J.. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (2005) “Archytas and Optics.” Science in Context, Vol. 18, No. 1, 35-53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castagnoli, L. (2016) “Aristotle on the Non-Cause Fallacy.” History and Philosophy of Logic, Vol. 37, No. 1, 9-32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (1999) “Aristotle’s Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.” Phronesis, Vol. 44, No. 3, 199-227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (2018) “Aristotle’s Psychology.” In A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. Kirkland, S. and Sanday, E.. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1984) Aristotle’s Philosophy of Action. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (2003) Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (2012) “Teleological Causation.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C. J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. (1946) Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato and the Academy. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, T. (2015) “Aristotle and the Ancient Puzzle about Coming to Be.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 49, 129-150.Google Scholar
Cleary, J. J. (1985) “On the Terminology of ‘Abstraction’ in Aristotle.” Phronesis, Vol. 30, No. 1, 13-45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleary, J. J. (1988) Aristotle on the Many Senses of Priority. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Code, A. (1976) “Aristotle’s Response to Quine’s Objections to Modal Logic.” Journal of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 5, No. 2, 159-186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. (1997) “The Priority of Final Causes over Efficient Causes in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals,” in Aristotelische Biologie, eds. Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S.. Stuttgart: Steiner.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. M. (2008) “Kooky Objects Revisited: Aristotle’s Ontology.” Metaphilosophy, Vol. 39, No. 1, 3-19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. M. (2009) “Substances.” In A Companion to Aristotle, ed. Anagnostopoulos, G.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Coope, U. (2004) “Aristotle’s Account of Agency in Physics III 3.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 20, No. 1, 201-227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coope, U. (2007) “Aristotle on Action.” Proceedings of Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, Vol. 81, No. 1, 109-138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corkum, P. (2008) “Aristotle on Ontological Dependence.” Phronesis, Vol. 53, No. 1, 65-92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corkum, P. (2012) “Aristotle on Mathematical Truth.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Vol. 20, No. 6, 1057-1076.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, C. (2007) Explaining the Brain. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. (1975) “On Some of Aristotle’s First Thoughts About Substances.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 84, No. 3, 372-413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. (1981) Time, Action and Necessity. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. (1991) “Can Physics Be Exact?” In La Physique d’Aristote et Les Conditions d’Une Science de la Nature, ed. de Gandt, F. and Souffrin, P.. Paris: Librarie philosophique J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. (1993) Language, Thought and Falsehood in Ancient Greek Philosophy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. (2003) “Aristotle on Modality: Never Will and Cannot.” The Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, Vol. 74, No. 1, 163-178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Distelzweig, P. M. (2013) “The Intersection of the Mathematical and Natural Sciences: The Subordinate Sciences in Aristotle.” Apeiron, Vol. 46, No. 2, 85-105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dudley, J. (2012) Aristotle’s Concept of Chance: Accidents, Causes, Necessity, and Determinism. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Ebert, T. (1998) “Aristotelian Accidents.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 16, 133-159.Google Scholar
Everson, S. (1997) Aristotle on Perception. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ferejohn, M. (2013) Formal Causes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernandez, P. and Mittelmann, J. (2017) “ἡ κίνησις τῆς τέχνης: Crafts and Souls as Principles of Change.” Phronesis, Vol. 62, No. 2, 136-169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, G. (1981) “Aristotle on Determinism: A Review of Richard Sorabji’s Necessity, Cause, and Blame.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 90, No. 4, 561-579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, G. (1987) “Forms as Causes: Plato and Aristotle.” In Mathematik und Metaphysik bei Aristoteles, ed. Graeser, A.. Berne and Stuttgart: Haupt.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (1993) On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Theory of Forms. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (1982) “Acts, Events and Things.” In Sprache und Ontologie. Akten des sechsten Internationalen Wittgenstein-Symposiums, 23. bis 30. August 1981, Kirchberg am Wechsel (Osterreich), ed. Leinfellner, W., Kraemer, E., and Schank, J.. Wien: Holder-Pichler-Tempsky.Google Scholar
Frede, D. (1985) “Aristotle on the Limits of Determinism: Accidental Causes in Metaphysics E 3.” In Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, ed. Gotthelf, A.. Pittsburgh, PA: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Frede, D. (1992) “Accidental Causes in Aristotle.” Synthese, Vol. 92, 39-62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M. (1980) “The Original Notion of Cause.” In Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, ed. Schofield, M., Burnyeat, M., and Barnes, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1985) “Aristotelian Actions.” Nous, Vol. 19, No. 3, 397-414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1991) “Accidental Causes and Real Explanations.” In Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, ed. Judson, L.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1953) The Foundations of Arithmetic. New York: Harper & Brothers.Google Scholar
Furth, M. (1988) Substance, Form and Psyche. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaskin, R. (1995) The Sea Battle and the Master Argument. Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1956) “Good and Evil.” Analysis, Vol. 17, No. 2, 33-42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1967) “Identity.” Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 21, No. 1, 3-12.Google Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1969) God and Soul. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1975) “Teleological Explanation.” In Explanation, ed. Korner, S.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1977) Providence and Evil. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1980) Reference and Generality. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Ginet, C. (1990) On Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldin, O. (1996) Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics 2.1-10. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1970) A Theory of Human Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1971) “The Individuation of Action.” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 68, No. 21, 761-774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1976) “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.” The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 30, No. 2, 226-254.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (2012) Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, W. (1975) “Counter-Predicability and Per Se Accidents.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. 57, 182-187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Granger, H. (1981) “The Differentia and the Per Se Accident in Aristotle.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. 63, 118-129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halper, E. (1993) Form and Reason: Essays in Metaphysics. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (1998) Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (2002) “Causation and Explanation in Aristotle.” Quaestio, Vol. 2, No. 1, 33-56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (2012) The Universe As We Find It. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heinaman, R. (1985) “Aristotle on Accidents.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 23, No. 3, 311-324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennig, B. (2017) “The Man Without Properties.” Synthese, Vol. 194, No. 6, 1989-2006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1973) Time and Necessity: Studies in Aristotle’s Theory of Modality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, C. (1996) “The Role of Contrast in Causal and Explanatory Claims.” Synthese, Vol. 107, No. 3, 395-419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hocutt, M. (1974) “Aristotle’s Four Becauses.” Philosophy, Vol. 49, No. 190, 385-399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, J. (1980) Actions. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Huismann, T. (2016) “Aristotle on Accidental Causation.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 2, No. 4, 561-575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huismann, T. (2021) “A New Puzzle About Aristotelian Accidents.” Metaphysics, Vol. 4, No. 1, 1-17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huismann, T. (2022a) “Aristotle on How Efficient Causation Works.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. 104, No. 4, 663-687.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huismann, T. (2022b) “The Texture of Aristotle’s Ontology.” Apeiron, Vol. 55, No. 4, 557-586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ide, H. (1993) “Aristotle Metaphysics vi 2–3 and Coincidences.” Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 13, 341-354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. (1988) Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. (2012) The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. (2005) Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. R. (2015) “Luck in Aristotle’s Physics and Ethics.” In Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, ed. Henry, D. and Nielsen, K.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Judson, L. (1991) “Chance and ‘Always or for the Most Part’ in Aristotle.” In Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, ed. Judson, L.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judson, L. (1998) “What Can Happen When You Eat Pungent Food.” In Aristotle on Logic, Language and Science, ed. Avgelis, N. & Peonidis, F.. Athens: Sakkoulas Publications.Google Scholar
Katz, E. (2017) “Ontological Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.” Phronesis, Vol. 62, No. 1, 26-68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2004) “The Argument of Metaphysics vi 3.” Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 24, 119-134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kress, E. (2020) “Aristotle on Spontaneous Generation, Spontaneity, and Natural Processes.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 58, 157-204.Google Scholar
Kress, E. (2021) “Thought, Choice, and Other Causes in Aristotle’s Account of Luck.” Apeiron, Vol. 54, No. 4, 615-648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lear, J. (1982) “Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 91, No. 2, 161-192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. (1982) “Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 20, No. 3, 219-238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. (1984) “Aristotle on Chance.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. 66, No. 1, 52-60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2010) Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. (1982) “Accidental Sameness in Aristotle.” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 42, No. 1, 1-36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. (1991) Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
List, C. and Menzies, P. (2009) “Nonreductive Physicalism and the Limits of the Exclusion Principle.” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 106, No. 9, 475-502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, H. (2015) “Natural Goals of Action in Aristotle.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 1, No. 4, 583-600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loux, M. J. (2008) Primary Ousia. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loux, M. J. (2012) “Substances, Coincidentals, and Aristotle’s Constituent Ontology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C. J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1980) The Cement of the Universe. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makin, S. (1993) Indifference Arguments. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Makin, S. (2018) “Potentiality in Aristotle’s Physics and Biology.” In Handbook of Potentiality, ed. Engelhardt, K. and Quante, M.. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Mansion, A. (1946) Introduction À La Physique Aristotélicienne, 2nd ed. Louvain: Éditions de l’Institut supérieur de Philosophie.Google Scholar
Marmodoro, A. (2014) Aristotle on Perceiving Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthews, G. B. (1982) “Accidental Unities.” In Language and Logos, eds. Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M.. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M. (1995) “Review: The Presocratics.” The Classical Review, Vol. 45, No. 2, 277-279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, J. (1921) The Nature of Existence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. (1997) “Properties and Predicates.” In Properties, ed. Mellor, D. H. and Oliver, A.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (2002) “Aristotle’s Definition of Soul and the Programme of De Anima.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 22, 83-139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, S. S. (1992) “Aristotle, Teleology, and Reduction.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 101, No. 4, 791-825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, S. S. (2011) Aristotle on Moral Responsibility: Character and Cause. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mignucci, M. (1981) “Hos epi to polu et nécessaire dans la conception aristotélicienne de la science.” In Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics. Padua: Editrice Antenore.Google Scholar
Mignucci, M. (1986) “Aristotle’s Definitions of Relatives in Cat. 7.” Phronesis, Vol. 31, No. 2, 101-127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, F. (1973) “Did Aristotle Have the Concept of Identity?The Philosophical Review, Vol. 82, No. 4, 483-490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, J. (1974) “Aristotle on Adequate Explanations.” Synthese, Vol. 28, No. 1, 3-17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mossel, B. (2001) “The Individuation of Actions.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 79, No. 2, 258-278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mueller, I. (1998) “Platonism and the Study of Nature (Phaedo 95e ff.).” In Method in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Gentzler, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nabokov, V. (1961) Nikolai Gogol. New York: New Directions Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Natali, C. (2004) “On Generation and Corruption I.6.” In Aristotle: On Generation and Corruption, Book I (Symposium Aristotelicum), ed. De Haas, F. and Mansfeld, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nielsen, K. M. (2017) “Spicy Food as Cause of Death: Coincidence and Necessity in Metaphysics E 2–3.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 52, 303-342.Google Scholar
Nutton, V. Ancient Medicine. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Oddie, G. (2013) “An Argument against Commensurate Truthmakers.” Presented at the 2013 APA Central Division Meeting, New Orleans, LA. February 23rd, 2013.Google Scholar
Odzuck, S. (2014) The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. (1986) Logic, Science and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Pasnau, R. (2011) Metaphysical Themes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pelletier, F. J. (1979) “Sameness and Referential Opacity in Aristotle.” Nous, Vol. 13, No. 3, 283-311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peramatzis, M. (2011) Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, S. (1985) “Substitution in Aristotelian Technical Contexts.” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 47, No. 2, 249-256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pols, A. J. K. (2013) “Choosing Your Poison and the Time of a Killing.” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 165, No. 3, 719-733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1960) Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. (2000) Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
van Rijen, J. (1989) Aspects of Aristotle’s Logic of Modalities. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, J. (2012) “Motion and Change in Aristotle’s Physics 5.1.” Phronesis, Vol. 57, No. 1, 63-99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, J. (2014) “Essence and End in Aristotle.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 46, 73-107.Google Scholar
Rossi, G. (2011) El azar según Aristóteles: Estructuras de la causalidad accidental en los procesos naturales y en la acción. Bonn, Germany: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Sauvé, S. (1987) “Unmoved Movers, Form, and Matter.” Philosophical Topics, Vol. 15, No. 2, 171-196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2005) “Contrastive Causation.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 114, No. 3, 327-358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2009) “On What Grounds What.” In Metametaphysics, ed. Manley, D.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Schnieder, B. (2009) “‘By’: A Refutation of the Anscombe Thesis.” Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 31, No. 6, 649-669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (1998) “Platonic Causes.” Phronesis, Vol. 43, No. 2, 114-132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. J. (1999) Order in Multiplicity: Homonymy in the Philosophy of Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Shields, C. J. (2012) “Being qua Being.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C. J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1980) Necessity, Cause and Blame. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Spellman, L. (1990) “Referential Opacity in Aristotle.” History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol. 7, No. 1, 17-32.Google Scholar
Stavrianeas, S. (2008) “Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle’s Biology.” Rhizai, Vol. 2, 303-338.Google Scholar
Stove, D. (1972) “Misconditionalisation.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 50, No. 2, 173-183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Strycker, É. (1968) “Concepts-clés et terminologie dans les livres ii à vii des Topiques.” In Aristotle on Dialectic: Proceedings of the Third Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Owen, G. E. L.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Studtmann, P. (2012) “Aristotle’s Categorial Scheme.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. Shields, C.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. (2003) “On Qualification.” Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 17, No. 1, 385-414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, J. J. (1997) “The Right and the Good.” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 94, 273-298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tichý, P. (1988) The Foundations of Frege’s Logic. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tierney, R. (2001) “On the Senses of ‘Symbebekos’ in Aristotle.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 21, 61-82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuozzo, T. (2014) “Aristotle and the Discovery of Efficient Causation.” In Efficient Causation: A History, ed. Schmaltz, T.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Urbanas, A. (1988) La notion d’accident chez Aristote. Montréal: Éditions Bellarmin.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. (2006) “Modern Moral Philosophy Again.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 106, No. 3, 345-362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterlow, S. (1982a) Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle’s Physics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterlow, S. (1982b) Passage and Possibility: A Study of Aristotle’s Modal Concepts. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedin, V. (1973) “A Remark on Per Se Accidents and Properties.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. 55, 30-35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedin, V. (2000) Aristotle’s Theory of Substance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiner, S. F. (2012) “Aristotle’s Metaphysics V 7 Revisited.” Apeiron, Vol. 48, No. 4, 407-426.Google Scholar
White, N. (1971) “Sameness and Oneness.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 80, No. 2, 177-197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, N. (1986) “Identity, Modal Individuation, and Matter in Aristotle.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. 11, No. 1, 475-494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wieland, W. (1975) “The Problem of Teleology.” In Articles on Aristotle, Volume 1: Science, ed. Barnes, J., Schofield, M., Sorabji, R.. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. (1967) Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wildberg, C. (2004) “On Generation and Corruption I.7: Aristotle on Poiein and Paschein.” In Aristotle: On Generation and Corruption, Book I (Symposium Aristotelicum), ed. De Haas, F. and Mansfeld, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williams, C. J. F. (1985) “Aristotle’s Theory of Descriptions.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 94, No. 1, 63-80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witt, C. (2018) Substance and Essence in Aristotle: An Interpretation of Metaphysics VII–IX. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2003) Making Things Happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (1992) “Mental Causation.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 101, No. 2, 245-280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Tyler Huismann, University of Oklahoma
  • Book: Aristotle on Accidental Causation
  • Online publication: 28 January 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009491464.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Tyler Huismann, University of Oklahoma
  • Book: Aristotle on Accidental Causation
  • Online publication: 28 January 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009491464.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Tyler Huismann, University of Oklahoma
  • Book: Aristotle on Accidental Causation
  • Online publication: 28 January 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009491464.011
Available formats
×