Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T12:18:30.079Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Hastening to the Gymnasium

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 March 2023

Noah Kaye
Affiliation:
Michigan State University

Summary

More than any other Hellenistic dynasty, the Attalids patronized city gymnasia. A much needed explanation for that curious philanthropic habit is provided, and it is argued that the Pergamenes helped transform the gymnasium into the “second agora” of the post-Classical polis. While the financial instability of the gymnasium and its agglomerative architectural ensemble made it an attractive target for royal donors, the ideological appeal was paramount. In the mid-second century BCE, the gymnasium may have represented itself as “the city writ small,” but this was a fiction, concocted by its elite membership and reinforced by the Attalids, ever anxious to present themselves as champions of the polis without ceding real power to the populace. The social distance of the gymnasium from other polis institutions was the critical factor for the entry of the Attalids, who partnered with towering civic benefactors to remake the space just as the royal capital reformed itself with a gymnasium as the anchor of the new urban plan.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Attalids of Pergamon and Anatolia
Money, Culture, and State Power
, pp. 234 - 282
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

They hastened to have a share in the unlawful ceremony at the summons of the discus calling them to the palaistra.

(2 Macc 4:41)

The Roman legate Gaius Sulpicius, Polybius tells us, was a man consumed, given over to madness, reveling in his quarrel with Eumenes II of Pergamon (31.6.5).Footnote 1 In 164, a perplexed Senate, facing a realignment of power in Asia Minor, dispatched Sulpicius to the region on a fact-finding mission.Footnote 2 On arrival, Sulpicius solicited allegations against the king by posting notices in the most important cities. Anyone who wished could come to Sardis at an appointed time and be heard. Sulpicius then retreated to the gymnasium of Sardis where he sat for 10 days, holding court and taking complaints. The Roman investigator appears to have been energetic, systematic, even primed for a fight, but mad? What to make of the characterization of Polybius? It no doubt reflects the depth of the Roman assault on the ideological underpinnings of Attalid power and indeed of the world in which the Achaean statesman had come of age. Wherein, then, lies that depth? It has long been noted that Sulpicius was appealing directly to Attalid subjects in Attalid territory.Footnote 3 The choice of Sardis as the venue must also have stung. The former satrapal capital had grown in significance under the Seleukids, and had acquired under the Attalids the distinction of a cistophoric mint, if not a royal residence.Footnote 4

Yet Sulpicius was not the first hot-tempered invader to occupy the gymnasium of Sardis. Antiochos III had even brought an army into its confines during the siege of 215/14.Footnote 5 Seleukid forces remained quartered in the gymnasium when Sardis fell, one new imposition among many that would have served to chasten its people for their disloyalty. The next year, however, Antiochos eased the city’s punitive fiscal burden, and simultaneously lightened the occupation. In both cases, the city’s gymnasium was a focus of his beneficence. He restored the gymnasium to the Sardians in its “former condition” – no mean feat – and he set life in the place on firm ground for the future. Much as he later did for Herakleia-under-Latmos, the king earmarked royal revenues for an oil fund (elaiochristion), one which would provide 200 metrêtai of oil to the neoi each year (SEG XXXVII 859; SEG XXXIX 1283 and 1285). Scholarship has always recognized the affections of Hellenistic kings for the gymnasium and “those who frequent it.”Footnote 6 The charged and politicized nature of this mode of interaction is on full display in the famous episode from Jerusalem (see the epigraph above), an incident roughly contemporaneous with the visit of Sulpicius to Sardis: a group of young Judean priests approached Antiochos IV as members of an incipient gymnasium under royal patronage; a cataclysm ensued.Footnote 7 Now, with the recent publication of the earmarking documents from Sardis and Herakleia, the subsequent discovery of more inscriptions relating to Attalid involvement with the gymnasium, it has become ever more clear that the institution of the gymnasium started to take on new significance ca. 200 BCE and, by mid-century, constituted a primary site of interaction between cities and kings. Though the evidence is sparse, this is very likely to have been the case in Sardis in 164. In the late 160s, the Attalids were making gifts in support of gymnasium life in places as distant and different as Rhodes, once an enemy and always a rival, and the city of Delphi, not to mention in “free” Miletus and Kos, or in Andros, a garrisoned possession. Indeed, not more than a few years before his arrival, the gymnasium where Sulpicius set up shop would have hosted competitions during the inaugural celebration of the Panathenaia kai Eumeneia festival, which honored the goddess Athena and the Attalid king.Footnote 8 Sulpicius’ presence in the gymnasium of Sardis was understood by all who observed as an affront – as it was meant to be, so much so, in fact, says Polybius, that the Greeks, as if for pity, rallied to the king (31.6.6).Footnote 9

The Problem of the Attalids and the Gymnasium

If Hellenistic kings’ interactions with the gymnasium, with the ephebate of the Greek city, and with the other institutions and groups that “had a share in the oil” form a pattern of behavior that extends across time and space, it is a pattern that is sharply pronounced among the Attalids, especially after 188.Footnote 10 Consider, by way of a contrast, how when the Seleukids came into control of Miletus, they set about rebuilding the city’s sanctuary of Apollo at Didyma, a god who happened to be their tutelary divinity. The Attalids, on the other hand, also sent a message to the Panhellenic audience, but by paying for a gymnasium in the urban center of Miletus: a promise to promote the identity of each and every polis.Footnote 11 Klaus Bringmann counts 29 foundations for gymnasia in his corpus of royal gifts.Footnote 12 Of these, an impressive 13 are Attalid (Graph 5.1). And we can add considerably to that count. The practice certainly goes back to the dynasty’s origins: Philetairos consecrated land in Thespiai to Hermes, god of the gymnasium par excellence, and earmarked its revenues for an oil fund.Footnote 13 Then, the practice intensified after Apameia: eight of the 13 foundations are securely dated post-188. In addition, the much-improved edition of the decree of Colophon for the Pergamene prince Athenaios now allows us to identify the royal gift of a paidikê (youth) palaistra in the background.Footnote 14 The decree for Korragos and the new documents from Metropolis and Toriaion show the integration of the polis gymnasium into the fiscal structures of the enlarged Attalid kingdom (D1, D5, and D8).Footnote 15 The Toriaion dossier may even illuminate RC 51, which Welles called a “letter of an Attalid king to military cleruchs, conferring various grants,” and which he dated to the second century BCE. Its fragmentary line 24 reads, “From which [revenue source] I have given oil to the neoi” (ὧν ἔδωκα τοῖς νέοις εἰς τὸ ἔλαιον).Footnote 16

Graph 5.1 Royal gifts to gymnasia.

(Data from Bringmann et al., 1995)

Still, to gauge the full extent of the Attalid interest in the gymnasium, we must consider several other categories of evidence. The first is the paper trail left by courtiers, which points to the gymnasium as an interface between kings, represented by their most trusted officials, and the public. The prime example is a lamentably fragmentary decree found in southeastern Lydia, which honors a well-connected courtier named Asklepides, who at the end of a long career in the service of the Attalids served as overseer of an unnamed city, perhaps Apollonia-on-the-Maeander. The inscription describes the by-then-deceased Asklepides as having been both a citizen of Pergamon and an intimate (syntethrammenos) of the future Attalos II.Footnote 17 The package of posthumous honors awarded to this courtier is full of references to the multiple gymnasia of the city. What is clear from this difficult text is that one or more of the gymnasia was slated to host rituals in memory of the courtier.Footnote 18 At once an extension of the king’s body and a representative of the citizenry of Pergamon, Asklepides found in the gymnasium of the unnamed polis an exquisitely convenient venue for local politics and the manufacture of collective memory.

Second, the archaeology of the gymnasium of the metropolis of Pergamon is a spectacular demonstration of the dynasty’s attachment to the institution. First excavated at the turn of the century, a recent German research project has intensively reinvestigated the space (Figs. 5.1 and 5.2).Footnote 19 Its cascade of three terraces supported by huge retaining walls, the product of the original design and investment of Eumenes II, placed the monument at the center of the ancient spectator’s visual encounter with the royal capital.Footnote 20 It evinces an unparalleled concern for the differentiation of space inside a gymnasium according to function, especially cultic. Room H seems to have housed the ruler cult, with statues of Eumenes and Philetairos next to one of Herakles.Footnote 21 Below, the sacred quarter of the Middle Terrace represents an unusual internal temenos. Crucially, it is the largest gymnasium on record in the Hellenistic world.Footnote 22 At ca. 20,000 m2, it approaches double the size of a normal city’s gymnasium.Footnote 23 With its three terraces and two temples, xystos and paradromis (running tracks), a precinct 212 m long at its greatest extent, and with an open-air palaistra measuring 35 × 75 m, it is in fact the largest integrated building complex in the entire city of Pergamon. Further, a recent revision of the city’s street plan highlights the central importance of the gymnasium to the city of Eumenes II. A decade of soundings and geophysical prospection have ruled out a grid plan with streets oriented toward towers on Eumenes’ wall. Instead, streets of various modules are oriented neatly toward the entrances and specific features of the gymnasium.Footnote 24 Set just below the old, so-called wall of Philetairos, which became, in effect, a lower boundary for the Upper/Old City with its palace district, religious monuments, and public spaces, the gigantism of the new gymnasium served to anchor the street plan and visual axes of the neighborhoods of the Lower/New City. The western entrance was fronted with a public fountain alongside the city’s main arterial road. Indeed, for the New City of Eumenes II and his successors, this gymnasium complex appears to have been the sole public space of note, with the date of the Lower Agora now fixed in the early Roman period.Footnote 25 Wörrle has recently argued that one of the principal functions of the Pergamene gymnasium was to strengthen polis identity in Pergamon, which is often difficult to discern elsewhere in the city.Footnote 26 This building project may be simply the most resplendent evidence of negotiations that took place in many cities between elites and the Attalids. Poliad identity achieved stable footing, but the bonds of dependence were also strengthened. The Großes Gymnasion dates to the period of downhill urban expansion under Eumenes II, and evidence for a third-century gymnasium at Pergamon is extremely thin, limited to a single inscription, dated by the notoriously unreliable criterion of letter forms (I.Pergamon 9).Footnote 27 On any reckoning, Eumenes II placed the gymnasium at the center of civic life in the polis of Pergamon. And yet only when the dynasty fell did responsibility for the oil fund pass from the royal treasury to the gymnasiarch.Footnote 28 The institution remained to the end a joint venture of king and citizenry.Footnote 29

Figure 5.1 Plan of the gymnasium of Pergamon in relation to adjacent monuments and current reconstruction of street grid.

(courtesy of Pergamon Excavation of the German Archaeological Institute; https://geoserver.dainst.org/maps/5548/view)

Figure 5.2 Gymnasium of Pergamon, looking east across the palaistra of the upper terrace.

(courtesy of Pergamon Excavation of the German Archaeological Institute; photo: Ulrich Mania)

Finally, indirect and circumstantial evidence of Attalid involvement with the gymnasium abounds. The city of Tralles can stand as a case study. It has produced a Hellenistic victor list, mentioning neoi, which Wilhelm Dittenberger dated to the second century, and possessed a gymnasium by the time of Augustus.Footnote 30 While the proximity of ancient Tralles to a modern Turkish military installation puts 65% of the site off-limits to archaeology, an impressive Roman bath–gymnasium complex has been identified. Throughout Asia Minor, complexes of this sort stand over the remains of Hellenistic gymnasia, in many cases, over a gymnasium that the Attalids are known to have patronized.Footnote 31 At Apameia, the Attalids received Tralles as a “gift,” stripping it of its Seleukid dynastic title, but adorning it with a cistophoric mint and a palace.Footnote 32 An ostotheke that was found 7 km east of Aydın/Tralles bears the names of several Attalid officials and their wives, attesting to the city’s importance as an administrative center with an open-air military camp on its outskirts.Footnote 33 In many ways, Tralles resembles Ephesus, where a gymnasium foundation is known only by indirect means, namely, through an ephebic dedication to (Hermes), Herakles, and King Eumenes.Footnote 34 Ephesus too was a gift city, and has produced epigraphic evidence for the local presence of royal officials, the hêgemônes and strategoi who dedicate to Eumenes II and Queen Stratonike (SEG XXXIII 942). It was an Ephesian neos that Attalos II considered the right kind of young man to be educated alongside the future Attalos III.Footnote 35 One can easily imagine that the king was just as familiar with the neoi of Tralles as he was with their coevals in Ephesus.

This chapter offers a new explanation for the profound connection between Pergamon and the gymnasium, which casts the Attalids as participants and agents of change in the social history of ancient Greece. It argues that benefaction of the gymnasium was one more way in which the Attalids deftly synched local, civic culture with imperial fiscal structures. This is a mode of interaction that is not exclusively, but rather characteristically Attalid.Footnote 36 What is unexplained is its efflorescence during the Pergamene floruit – and what longer-term effects Pergamon may have had on this famous incubator of Hellenes. To date, scholarship has identified the pattern, but neither explained it adequately nor charted the ramifications. One has long struggled to divine the motivations behind individual royal gifts.Footnote 37 Nevertheless, the Attalid affinity for the gymnasium is usually understood, first, as a straightforward expression of Pergamene Panhellenism and, second, as part of a general tendency among Hellenistic kings to use the gymnasium to manufacture loyal, worshipping subjects. To take but two examples, Robert calls the gymnasium “this characteristic edifice of Greek culture” and “the place set aside for the royal cult and demonstrations of loyalty toward the Hellenistic kings.”Footnote 38 For Dreyer, the kings wanted to use the gymnasium “to create bonds of loyalty by influencing children and the youth, and to recommend themselves to the adult citizens as benefactors and supporters of Greek culture.”Footnote 39 Both statements collapse the evolution of the gymnasium into a synchronic snapshot. It is a remarkable fact that for Aristotle in the fourth century BCE, the gymnasium was not an essential feature of the polis.Footnote 40 For the city’s takeover of the gymnasium was a process transpiring over the course of the philosopher’s life. By contrast, for Pausanias, writing in the second century CE about the modest settlement of Panopeas in Phokis, a proper polis needed a gymnasium.Footnote 41 Between the age of Aristotle and the time of Pausanias, a major change occurred. Did the Attalids spur or accelerate it?

There is no denying that the Attalids represented themselves as the avatars of the Greeks.Footnote 42 One aspect of their Kulturpolitik was to establish themselves in centers of international significance to Hellenes, such as Delphi, Delos, and later Athens, and to pose as the champions of the Hellene in the never-ending war against the Barbarian – in their day, figured as the Galatian. In these respects, their politics were Panhellenic, as Lynette Mitchell understands the term. In her study of the origin and development of concepts of Panhellenism in Archaic and Classical Greece, Mitchell stresses “the very complexity and flexibility of Panhellenism that makes it so difficult, on the one hand, to define, and, on the other, to control.”Footnote 43 Key elements of an earlier Panhellenic ideology remained vital in the Hellenistic period, chief among them, the related themes of supra-poliad unity (koinê homonoia) and commitment to a war of liberation against the Barbarian, both spelled out in Chremonides’ decree of 269/8 (IG II2 686 + 687).Footnote 44 These may be the wellsprings of the visual rhetoric of Attalid art, but they will not help explain Attalid involvement with the gymnasium.Footnote 45 Some might imagine a cultural Panhellenism behind this behavior, a concern to unify Hellenes around a shared paideia in the nascent Library of the capital as much as in the gymnasia of the cities. We should not confuse motivation with effect. In the most general terms, the gymnasium created and sustained a Panhellenic community of shared cultural practice. But by patronizing the gymnasia, the Attalids were sustaining polis identities, not suppressing them. Paradoxically, Pergamene ideology was by no means supra-poliad; it exalted particularism. For Polybius, Eumenes II was his generation’s greatest royal benefactor of Greek cities (poleis Hellênidas) (32.8.5).Footnote 46

There is also no denying that the gymnasium cemented the loyalties of Attalid subjects, but it tied people to Pergamon even as it enhanced their sense of belonging to a particular polis. Young men who enjoyed a youth spent in a palaistra equipped at royal expense – on the condition that they parade and sacrifice to the king on his birthday – were bound to fall into line as adults. Yet this drastically reduces the complexity of their experience. Young men may have been wrestling beneath portrait statues of the royal family, but they were also preparing for close combat under teachers picked by the city that they swore to defend.Footnote 47 By patronizing the gymnasium, the Attalids did not create an impassive and apolitical elite. In fact, they produced bands of neaniskoi, crack troops, the fighting force of the young men’s association.Footnote 48 These neaniskoi might defend royal affairs (basilika pragmata), as they did in Ionian Metropolis during the War of Aristonikos, or, alternatively, they might pursue the specific military objectives of their home cities.Footnote 49 Sometimes, we cannot tell which it was, or whether it might have been both. For example, in the letter of Eumenes II to the polis of the Tabênoi (?), the mysteriously named neaniskoi tôn oikeiôn (“of the clan”), fought under a local big man/courtier named Koteies against the Galatians.Footnote 50 Patrice Hamon, however, has provided a new reading of the text, which also sees the group “going out against Apameia (προσελήλυθ’ [ἐ]π̣’ Ἀπάμειαν),” that is, attacking another city.Footnote 51 At any rate, the society of the gymnasium, while influential, represented a small share of the kingdom’s population. If loyalty alone were at stake, the Attalids would have been much better off putting their money elsewhere. Surely, grain funds or important public buildings such as bouleuteria (council houses) were gifts better suited for the desired result.

Recent scholarship on the Hellenistic polis, with its insistence on the survival and vitality of polis institutions after the Battle of Chaironeia (338 BCE), proposes a different explanation. For Andrzej Chankowski, the cities of Asia Minor stood to gain the most from the interaction.Footnote 52 In his model, unlike the gymnasia of the cities of Antigonid Macedonia or of the Syracusan epikrateia, the gymnasia of Attalid cities produced citizen soldiers. In other words, the civic institution lay outside the recruitment structure of the royal army. And because the cities profited the most, so the argument goes, civic initiative and agency must lie behind this pattern of royal behavior. In short, the gymnasium survived because it helped the polis survive; Attalid patronage simply tracked alongside.Footnote 53 Yet the case of Toriaion (D8), on which the argument hinges, in fact points up the weakness of any explanation founded on assumptions of cui bono. Eumenes II offered to provide Toriaion with several ready-made institutions, among them, an oil fund that he supported with an earmark. While Chankowski recognizes the gift as evidence of the Attalids’ active promotion of the gymnasium, he reduces Eumenes to an automaton.Footnote 54 The king may have had a model in mind, but not one invented in his own chancery. Rather, we must imagine, Eumenes adopted a model of interaction that took shape in cities such as Herakleia-under-Latmos in the third century.Footnote 55 For Chankowski, Toriaion demonstrates once again the inability of the kings to come up with their own ideas in the face of the “vitality of the institutions of the polis.” The popularity of the gymnasium “in and of itself” justified the choice.Footnote 56 On this account, the Hellenistic kings affected neither the diffusion nor the shape of an institution born fully formed in fourth-century Athens.

The search for the prime mover in this interaction is futile. For new poleis, we can only guess at what preceded the formalization of the gymnasium in places such as Phrygia, Cappadocia, or Judaea.Footnote 57 For the old, coastal poleis of Asia Minor, our first glimpse of the institution is often no earlier than the second century BCE.Footnote 58 Instead, we ought to seek models for the Hellenistic polis that reflect more faithfully the staggered vision of polis actors: local concerns in the foreground, but the king, ever present, on the horizon.Footnote 59 Our challenge is to make plain the links between local and high politics that were once so obvious. Our difficulty in so doing is acute when it comes to the king and the gymnasium. For example, one has struggled to understand why third-century Halikarnassos asked “King Ptolemy” for “permission (synchôrein)” to renovate its gymnasium, “so that the neoi should have a gymnasium and the paides should reclaim the paidikê palaistra that the neoi are currently using.”Footnote 60 The city had sent an embassy to the king before it announced a public subscription.Footnote 61 This is a curious detail. In what sense did Halikarnassos need royal permission to renovate its gymnasium? Léopold Migeotte, plausibly, suspects that the Halikarnassians were fishing for a contribution from the king, which they may well have obtained.Footnote 62 What we know for certain is that the king figured from the beginning in the city’s planning. It is unclear in which sense, if any, they were required to contact Alexandria before undertaking a public works project that would marshal the city’s resources and loyalties. The course of action, it seems, simply implied royal participation. In the panorama of their city that Halikarnassos presented to Ptolemy, the king could find himself.

To explain the Attalids’ promotion of the gymnasium by recourse to its popularity is to risk a circular argument. Indeed, the institution reached the peak of its popularity in the second century, with an ephebate attested in 65 cities. Yet surely royal – and especially Attalid – patronage and promotion helped swell the ranks. Consequently, the gymnasium as we know it is also an artifact of Hellenistic monarchy. An institution that we usually think of as quintessentially civic was transformed by the kings it eventually outlived. The second-century Attalids encountered this institution at a particular point in its development. This was not the ephebeia of late Classical Athens or Eretria, which molded large age classes into the core of the citizen-army, some 500–600 young men at a time in Lykourgan Athens, as the gymnasium found architectural expression in the urban enceinte for the first time.Footnote 63 For that institution, Nigel Kennell’s formulation “citizen training system” is more apt.Footnote 64 Nor was this yet the gymnasium of the period that the French have named the basse époque héllenistique (late and sub-Hellenistic), a gymnasium in which cities buried their greatest benefactors and rendered them a founder-hero’s cult, a space that Robert famously labeled the “second agora.”Footnote 65 To understand the efflorescence of Attalid involvement with the gymnasium we need to marry high political history to a deeper understanding of the development of this institution. Perhaps an Attalid political culture that fostered ties with civic elites is part of the story.Footnote 66 But the other dynasties needed their civic elites too, and their kings too could strike a civic pose in a local gymnasium. After all, the Antigonids Philip V and Perseus had their names inscribed on a donor list in the gymnasium of Larisa, without formal distinction, just like ordinary citizens.Footnote 67 In what follows, I analyze the role and functioning of the gymnasium in cities both inside and outside the territory allotted to the Attalids at Apameia. Sulpicius, the Roman disrupter in Sardis, came to meet Attalid subjects where they were accustomed to meeting their king.Footnote 68 How that had come to be the normal state of affairs has not been adequately explained.

The Gymnasium as a Civic Institution

When the ambassadors of Eumenes II approached the assembly (plêthos) of the Achaeans in 185 to offer an endowment, which would in the future pay the wages of the league’s Council (boulê), they were shouted down (Polyb. 22.7–8; Diod. Sic. 29.17).Footnote 69 The arguments of Apollonidas of Sikyon had won the day. Apollonidas had cast the gift as, in principle, worthy of the Achaeans but, in practice, given the identity of the donor and the purpose of the endowment, both utterly shameful and totally illegal (paranomotatê) (Polyb. 22.8.1–2). The Achaeans, he pointed out, had laws (nomoi) that prohibited archons and private individuals from accepting a king’s gift (dôra). The Achaean Council, then, as a collection of private individuals acting in their capacity as archons, had no business accepting one. Now, we know that the Achaeans were far from allergic to royal beneficence – they had been accepting Ptolemaic gold for years.Footnote 70 For Apollonidas and his camp, however, the form of the Attalid gift was unacceptable. It threatened to undermine the autonomy of the boulê, as gift obligated countergift, and to invite more unwanted royal advances: this year it was Eumenes II, but next year, warned Apollonidas, it would be Prousias, and then Seleukos. An Achaean civic institution would become unmoored.

We can consider, by way of contrast, that in 161/0 the Rhodians accepted a gift of grain from this same Eumenes. Proceeds from the sale of the grain were earmarked for an education fund, the instruction, presumably, taking place at least in part in the gymnasium (Polyb. 31.31). The critic of this gift is no Rhodian but Polybius himself, who takes the Rhodians to task for abandoning their usual sense of decency (to prepon). In his view, they had acted indecently in soliciting money (eranizesthai) for the education of their sons when none was lacking.Footnote 71 Were the arguments of Apollonidas of Sikyon about Attalid interference in the Achaean Council on the mind of the Achaeans historian, as Frank Walbank suggests?Footnote 72 Probably not. Polybius finds fault with the recipient, not the donor. Moreover, as has been pointed out, Polybius makes his critique from the standpoint of private morality.Footnote 73 It is a critique, however, that he applies to the body politic (politeia) – and not without reason. The Rhodians who secured the gift from Eumenes were acting more like private individuals than representatives of the state, hence the metaphor of Polybius: the philos (friend/kin/associate) who inappropriately seeks an eranos-loan from his fellow eranistai.Footnote 74 Whereas Apollonidas had nomos as law to buttress his claim, Polybius had merely nomos as custom, the inarticulate rules of philia (friendship). Apollonidas speaks only of high politics (pragmata), invoking the warring natures (enantiai physeis) of king and democracy (22.8.6). Polybius speaks of the conduct of fathers on behalf of sons (31.31.1). They were arguing about two entirely different species of civic institution.Footnote 75

The moralizing of Polybius on the Rhodians and Eumenes II throws into high relief the distinctiveness of the gymnasium as a civic institution in the decades after Apameia. Despite what the wooden language of polis decrees would have us believe, neither the membership nor the interests of the gymnasium were identical with the body politic. The gymnasium had its own law; even when subjected to the law of the polis, it retained its own norms; and its ideology, in a world where most cities and koina called themselves democracies, was elitist.Footnote 76 Its collective psychology and heroic archetypes were antisocial.Footnote 77 Its doors were literally closed to certain citizens, but unlike those of the Achaean Council, never to kings. If it was for Pausanias, in the second century CE, the sine qua non of the polis, it had not been for Aristotle, in the fourth century BCE.Footnote 78 For the Hellenistic period, one cannot assume that each and every polis contained a gymnasium.Footnote 79 Gauthier, more than any other scholar, has recognized the peculiar separateness of the gymnasium as a civic institution. He writes of gymnasia that function “outside the cadre of the polis,” the activities of which are but partially or even “in no way civic.”Footnote 80 His insight comes across in editions of various texts – honorific decrees of the city of Xanthos for Lyson and of Colophon for Athenaios, for example – and in his prolegomenon to the study of the institution.Footnote 81 In stark contrast, much recent scholarship emphasizes the civic character of the gymnasium without qualification.Footnote 82 For Hans Gehrke, the gymnasium is not quite the city in miniature, but close.Footnote 83 The catalog of Kennell is billed as a list of “state-run systems of citizen training.Footnote 84

We must contend with the distinctiveness of the gymnasium as a civic institution if we are to understand how it became a privileged site of contact with the Attalids. This is precisely why the only systematic attempt to analyze gymnasium society in its ambiguous and even oppositional relationship to civic society at large, Riet van Bremen’s analysis of the neoi, is also the only treatment to give court and king their due.Footnote 85 We often count the gymnasium as one of the central institutions of the Hellenistic polis. In the case of Lysimachus and the city of Nikaia in Bithynia, Strabo tells us, the panoptic, geographic center of the entire urban plan was a single stone at the center of the gymnasium.Footnote 86 Yet this very centrality remains difficult to understand. The Korragos decree (D1) shows that a city could plausibly argue to have had a gymnasium “from the beginning.” We in fact know that Toriaion did have one from the beginning (D8). It may not have been a sine qua non, but it was also far from superfluous. Because in hard times too it was important to have one, Philetairos gave the Cyzikenes 20 talents for oil and a gathering (synagôgê) during the Galatian crisis of the 270s.Footnote 87 And in calmer times, the resumption of gymnasium life was a sign that things had returned to normal: recall that after Antiochos III’s siege of Sardis the restoration of the gymnasium took priority. The gymnasium was also central because interactions with royal power were central to the political economy of the Hellenistic polis. Paradoxically, these interactions tended to take place in the gymnasium because it remained on the periphery of social and political life as long as kings stalked its peristyle colonnades.

Financing the Gymnasium

If we are willing to hazard a few generalizations about the Hellenistic gymnasium, we can identify several regional and historical trends.Footnote 88 One such trend is the gradual elaboration of this institution, throughout the Hellenistic world, from the Classical transition to the second century BCE, manifest in the construction of ever more rooms and the appearance of the first gymnasia in stone. We can observe an increasing complexity in administrative practice and an increase in scale: more instruction, more festivals – more activity. All of this would seem to imply a commensurate increase in financing, if not financial sophistication. Yet the reality was much messier. For gymnasiarchs, there were new responsibilities mandated both by the terms of private foundations, which added events to the calendar, and by law, not just the law of the gymnasium but the law of the polis. For instance, each year, officials of the gymnasium of Tauromenion in Sicily were required to document with an inscription both the number of their competitions and the impact on the budget, all in compliance with an ordinance known as the dogma neaniskôn.Footnote 89 On Athenian Delos, admittedly a special case, the gymnasiarch was both the primary agonothete of the island and chief administrator of gymnasium life.Footnote 90 An honorary decree for the gymnasiarch of 157/6 praises him for having accomplished all of the sacrifices, “which the laws and decrees of the demos had prescribed for him (ὅσας προσέταττον αὐτῶι οἱ τε νόμοι καὶ ψηφίσματα τοῦ δήμου)” (SEG XLVII 1218 lines 16–17).Footnote 91 Similarly, the gymnasiarch of Attalid Andros performed his sacrifices to the royal family “according to the laws (ἐ[κ] τῶν νόμων)” (D9 line 10).

As the responsibilities grew, so too did the prospects for failure. In a thorough review of the finances of the gymnasium, Schuler identifies the appearance of new controls and greater centralization in the second century, a response to a demonstrable weakness in the institution’s ability to sustain itself.Footnote 92 In particular, he adduces the cases of Beroia and Iasos, where the polis assumed tighter control of a gymnasium that had either lost or mismanaged funds.Footnote 93 Here, arguments about the strength and vitality of the institution fall flat. The neoi and presbyteroi of Iasos were quite explicit in their statement to their city’s boulê and demos: they could not do it on their own; their best attempt at accounting for the money, a process of review called διόρθωμα, had been unsuccessful.Footnote 94 Neither association had been able to recover the public money (koina chrêmata) that it had lent out. Generally, new regulations were a response to the problem, as the administrative techniques and habits of accountability were transferred from the polis to the gymnasium. But we might also see new regulations as one of the causes of financial meltdown in the first place. In this new era, the gymnasiarch who administered public funds would be held to the standards of the polis.Footnote 95 Meanwhile, he oversaw a patrimony that was a patchwork of foundations, dues, and ad hoc gifts. For those who had to manage the money, the financial hodgepodge of the Hellenistic gymnasium was sometimes more of a liability than an asset.Footnote 96

The financial shortcomings of the Hellenistic gymnasium are no secret. We have several examples of building projects paused, if finally completed. No doubt there were many that were abandoned, and so we lack an honorific decree or a donor’s dedication. In the aforementioned case of Halikarnassos, a local benefactor provided stopgap funding when the public subscription, and perhaps also the appeal to Ptolemy, failed. Indeed, royal benefactors were not entirely reliable, as Priene learned when several second-century monarchs reneged on their promises.Footnote 97 Yet the problem was not confined to large projects – to “people getting in over their heads.” The month-to-month and year-to-year operation of the gymnasium was a relentless challenge. We can see the ensuing financial bind in the Thessalian city of Pherai, in its early second-century list of gymnasiarchs “since the time of Alexander the Great.”Footnote 98 In several years, the list reads, μετέλιπε; the strange form is a hapax, but one easy to interpret: in those years, there was no gymnasiarch, perhaps no activity at all.Footnote 99 In effect, the city did not merely countenance a closure of the gymnasium; it preserved the memory. Another year, the list reads, ἁ πόλις. In this year, the city was prepared to play an unusually large role as the sole funder of the gymnasium.Footnote 100

As Olivier Curty’s study of the office demonstrates, it was only the most generous of gymnasiarchs, men such as Adaios of Amphipolis, who assumed the cost of a regular and continuous supply of oil from the beginning until the end of a term.Footnote 101 Accordingly, when faced with the inevitable shortfall, members of the gymnasium had several options. They could appeal to the city for help, which was the solution in Pherai, but also in Beroia and Iasos.Footnote 102 Or they could turn to “crowd sourcing,” with participants paying more or even all of the costs.Footnote 103 Or, finally, they could turn to benefactors, either local or royal, who tended to set up foundations. If managed well, these foundations ensured smooth functioning. Yet, as Schuler points out, benefactors with broader horizons might have their own ideas about the management of the money.Footnote 104 He cites the micro-managed case of Pharsalos, where Leonidas of Halikarnassos, a man with mercantile connections, insisted that city magistrates called tagoi and tamiai (treasurers), not the gymnasium crowd, manage his foundation.Footnote 105 In this way, the gymnasium could lean on the fiscal structures and competence of the city to solve its problems. We should not underestimate, however, the advantages accruing to the gymnasium from its incorporation into a system of royal finance. In fact, royal benefaction could qualitatively change the institution, rather than simply grow it. Once integrated into the Attalid fiscal system, some of the typical precariousness of bookkeeping disappeared. This is one lesson that can be drawn from the earmarking episode of Eumenes II in Toriaion (D8). When the king takes charge of organizing an oil fund, he has at his disposal not just resources, the revenue of the agoranomia or various tracts of chora basilikê, but the financial know-how of his officials (the hemiolios), and a flexibility that no city or individual could ever match.Footnote 106

The creation of royal as much as civic bonds of dependence marked a departure from what seems to have been a merely notional state of autarky. If the patrimony of the mid-Hellenistic gymnasium consisted of a mixed bag of foundations and subsidies from various quarters, the money that the city might provide, termed gymnasiarchikon, vel sim., was always supplemented from elsewhere.Footnote 107 In other words, the city’s contribution was not expected to cover the entire budget of the gymnasium. Kings, local benefactors, or the membership itself invariably picked up different costs. By the same token, the monarch’s gifts alone were not sufficient. For example, Ptolemaic soldiers of the local garrison tacked on an impressive 4,656 drachmas to a foundation of Ptolemy VI for the gymnasium of Thera.Footnote 108 In another case, a sensational lease document from Attalid Teos, excavated in 2016, shows a valuable piece of real estate in the gymnasium’s property portfolio. The neoi and other gymnasium members (metechontes tou gymnasiou) were mandated to offer the land with its built structures for at least 150 drachmas of annual rent, but raised 450 drachmas at auction.Footnote 109 Yet gauging financial independence is difficult since we lack even a single complete inventory of a given gymnasium’s resources. Instead, it is more fruitful to investigate the issue of control or ownership of this complex patrimony. To do so, we must consider the case of Beroia in the decades before 168/7.Footnote 110 The Macedonian city has produced the very richest documentation, showing that the gymnasium’s members – rather than the polis or the Antigonid king in Pella – controlled and effectively owned this wealth.

The basic purpose of the famous law of Beroia was to transform the gymnasiarch into a civic magistrate and thereby subject him to civic controls on the administration of patrimony. Of the old regime, we are not informed, but one assumes that the gymnasiarch’s election had taken place in the cadre of the gymnasium.Footnote 111 The first words of the law (nomos) proper change all that: Ἡ̣ πόλις αἱρείσθω γυμνασίαρχον (“The polis shall select the gymnasiarch”) (Side A lines 22–23). From now on, the gymnasiarch will submit accounts three times per year to a board of city auditors (exetastai) (Side B lines 91–97).Footnote 112 In the event that he must pay a fine for maladministration, a city official, the politikos praktôr, will exact it (Side B lines 96–103). Yet these measures seem to be the extent of the city’s new involvement. One of the law’s stated aims is to prevent wasteful use of the “revenues (prosodoi) of the neoi” (Side A lines 13–14). Some of the means of regulating these prosodoi may now be civic, but the patrimony itself is never conceptualized as such. It remains, throughout the text, the possession of the neoi (Side A lines 13–14, 30–31; Side B lines 60, 86–97).Footnote 113 The key passage is Side B lines 86–97, which sets out guidelines for the administration of the prosodoi of the neoi. It begins, Κυριευ|έτω δὲ ὁ γυμνασίαρχος τῶν προσόδων ὑπαρχουσῶν τοῖς νέοις καὶ̣ ἀπὸ τούτων|ἀναλισκέτω (“for the duration of his term, the gymnasiarch shall be kyrios [owner/executor] of the revenues, and he shall spend from them”). What money is left at the end of the year is combined with fines, and the next gymnasiarch becomes kyrios of the total (plêthos).Footnote 114 In other words, the money never passes through city coffers. Control of the patrimony of the gymnasium passes directly from one gymnasiarch to the next, even under the newly centralized regime. Moreover, if the gymnasiarch himself pays a fine, he pays it to the neoi (ἀποτινέτω τοῖς νέοις [Side B line 95]).Footnote 115

The law presents an ironclad distinction between the “revenues of the neoi” and the “revenues of the city.”Footnote 116 Gauthier goes so far as to argue that the burden of financial surveillance remains with les habitués du gymnase. He draws attention to three men who are elected in an assembly in the gymnasium (ekklêsia en tôi gymnasiôi) and who, presumably, take their oaths of office before that same body. These men are charged with the stringently quotidian tasks of helping the gymnasiarch keep watch over the neoi and over their finances (Side A lines 35–62). Yet unlike the gymnasiarch, they are not civic magistrates.Footnote 117 Furthermore, neoi or affiliated alumni would seem to play an important role in the auditing process, since the law permits “whoever wishes to do so to inspect the accounts of the gymnasiarch along with the exetastai (the city’s auditors) (ἐάν τινες βούλωνται, μετὰ τού|των συνεγλογίζεσθαι αὐτόν)” (Side B lines 92–93). The record of the final rendering of accounts is displayed on a notice board (sanis) in the gymnasium. Over the course of the next 24 months, anyone may contest in court (euthunein) the accuracy of these accounts (Side B lines 107–9). Consequently, whoever brings such a claim will have spent time in the gymnasium, if only to inspect the public record. Finally, Gauthier ascribes to the ὁ βουλόμενος (“he who so desires”) in Side B line 92 sole responsibility for reporting to the civic praktôr malfeasance discovered during the quadrimestral audits.Footnote 118 This has the effect of greatly limiting the role of the civic exetastai, which is why Pierre Fröhlich believes that the responsibility of these officials is simply implied.Footnote 119 Clearly, the very law that transformed the gymnasiarch into a civic magistrate, ultimately, preserved and enshrined many self-regulating aspects of the institution.

Despite the fact that the case of Beroia is unique in terms of these rich details, it still allows us to generalize. In fact, the law’s motivation clause is explicit on this point: ἐν αἷς πόλεσιν γυμνάσιά|ἐστιν καὶ̣ ἄλειμμα συνέστηκεν οἱ γυμνασιαρχι v|κοὶ̣ νόμοι κεῖνται ἐν τοῖς δημοσίοις, καλῶς ἔχει καὶ̣ πα|ρ᾽ ἡμῖν τὸ αὐτὸ συντελεσθῆναι “(Since) … in those cities in which there are gymnasia and an oil fund established, there are gymnasiarchal laws in the public archives, so it is fitting that for us too it should be accomplished” (Side A lines 6–9). The stated goal of the law was to bring the institutions of Beroia into alignment with those of other poleis. Moreover, we have no reason to believe that these other cities were exclusively Macedonian or Antigonid. On the contrary, because its teachers were itinerant and its benefactors elite and therefore cosmopolitan, the gymnasium developed in a very broad context.Footnote 120 It is true that Philip V (and Perseus?) took an unusually heavy-handed approach to the gymnasium, laboring to standardize certain aspects of ephebic and gymnasium life in Antigonid cities.Footnote 121 For this reason, Andrzej Chankowski argues that models elaborated on the basis of the Beroia law have limited applicability.Footnote 122 Yet the law itself (notoriously) never mentions the king. And while we should not rule out royal support for the Beroia gymnasium, the text is silent on this score. It depicts a city in the process of assuming a certain measure of control over a gymnasium in its midst. The law is both witness to the strength of polis identity under monarchic rule and to the jealousy with which the gymnasium guarded its financial independence.Footnote 123

Adorning the Gymnasium

When the gymnasiarch on Attalid Andros received his honors, it was, as is so often the case, because he had performed exceptionally. He had exceeded his duties. As the decree describes his accomplishment, in the shorthand of insiders, he had “embellished the gymnasium (τὸ γυμνάσιον κεκόσμηκεν)” (D9 line 6). He had added to it. In this instance, this meant building an entryway (pylôn) and dedicating an exedra and a statue of the king in a luminous variety of marble.Footnote 124 The language of kosmêsis, of adornment and elaboration, is familiar to the epigraphy of the gymnasium, where one, it seems, can always add something.Footnote 125 The material basis of its life was of course oil; without oil, the gymnasium, in fact, ceased to exist.Footnote 126 Therefore, a great variety of arrangements grew up to ensure a consistent supply of quality oil, many of them involving kings.Footnote 127 It has even become a matter of dispute whether one can assume that any other royal gift to a gymnasium was, by default, supplementary to an earlier gift of oil. For example, the honorific decree of Colophon for Menippos mentions “royal banquets (basilika deipna)” in the gymnasium, evidence of a late Attalid endowment.Footnote 128 While Bringmann et al. see a gift of oil accompanying the banquet endowment, Filippo Canali de Rossi has criticized their interpretation.Footnote 129 Regardless, a king who had already seen to the provision of oil – or found a gymnasium well stocked – could choose another form of embellishment. That he had so many options at his disposal speaks to the distinctiveness of the gymnasium as an institution.

Scholarship on the Hellenistic gymnasium has accounted for the many costs associated with the gymnasium: those which were fixed, such as oil, wood for heating baths, and water, and those that were a boon, such as renovations, distributions of food and drink, and so on.Footnote 130 However, we have perhaps not yet appreciated the sheer size of the institution’s appetite for benefaction, at least from the second century on. We know, for example, that the gymnasium could scarcely function without pay for teachers. So, cities very often took charge of this aspect of gymnasium finance.Footnote 131 In Delphi, the foundation of Attalos II provided wages for teachers (Syll.3 233). But one could always hire more specialized teachers, from farther afield, who commanded higher salaries. The Boeotian Koinon even mandated, it seems, that its member cities do so, which implies that local, cheaper teachers sufficed in the absence of outside intervention.Footnote 132 As a rule, what was necessary could always stand for improvement. The provision of water is another case in point. Specific body care practices necessitated a secure supply of water.Footnote 133 So it is no surprise that royal benefactors took pains to keep the water flowing, as Philip III seems to have done in Mylasa. In a land grant of 318/17, the king stipulated that the grant-holder provide water from a fountain on his land to a gymnasium and palaistra down the line.Footnote 134 Yet where the prestige of the dynasty was at stake, as in the city of Pergamon, or on the incredible ship of Hieron II, the Syrakousia, with its floating gymnasium, a king could always add more lavish means of water conveyance.Footnote 135 Proximity to water had always affected topography, but the second century witnessed a major uptick in the construction of bathing facilities set within gymnasium complexes.Footnote 136 Effectively, one could fill up the ritual calendar of the gymnasium. Various kings, Attalids among them, seem to have succeeded in doing just that on Kos.Footnote 137 Space, by contrast, was more readily available, especially if one built vertically on the dramatic, terraced slopes of the Hellenistic gymnasium. Perhaps, the peristyle around a palaistra could accommodate only so many exedrae. But one could always build new rooms, rooms with specific functions and higher prestige, such as a library, an ephêbikê exedra (instruction room), or the akroaterion (audience room) that the Attalids are believed to have financed at Aigai.Footnote 138 Or instead of rooms, the benefactor could provide entire buildings: a gymnasium for the presbyteroi to match that for the neoi; or a paidikê palaistra where one was lacking, as in Attalid Colophon, where the Homereion had to suffice until Athenaios’ purpose-built structure was finished.Footnote 139 The gymnasium offered seemingly endless opportunities for kosmêsis, and so for the display of royal virtue.

Social Status and the Gymnasium

When the Attalid dynasty fell, the gymnasium of Pergamon became a meeting place for self-styled aristoi andres (“best men”).Footnote 140 Yet if the membership had changed, it had in fact become more demotic with an influx of new citizens.Footnote 141 However, what remained the same was the current of aristocratic agonism that had long animated the civic gymnasium.Footnote 142 This was not so much the “citizen training system” as the nursery of the self-styled “beautiful and noble aristocratic youth” (kalokagathikos neos). From the mid-second century, it was a key context for the production of a new hereditary aristocracy, which successfully distinguished itself from an indistinct mass of citizens.Footnote 143 For example, the biography of Menippos of Colophon, who as a mere neos served on embassies to the Attalid capital, narrativizes how a youth’s aristocratic virtue might redound to his city’s credit.Footnote 144 Nevertheless, if for lack of status or simply money, a young citizen could not participate in its elitist culture, the gymnasium was happy to leave him untrained. In Beroia, the gymnasium excluded broad categories of people, some of whom must have included citizens: the freedman, the freedman’s son, the physically unfit (apalaistros), the drunkard, the madman, anyone who had prostituted themselves, and, importantly, anyone who plied a manual or common trade (agoraia technê).Footnote 145 In other words, citizenship did not guarantee admission – not even de jure.Footnote 146 The social stigma attached to banausic labor surely prevented many from entrance, as perhaps so too did a property qualification adumbrated in the Ephebic Law of Amphipolis.Footnote 147 On the other hand, one could grow up to be a citizen without passing through the gymnasium. Mid-third-century Athens minted just two dozen ephebes per year.Footnote 148 Surely, the body politic was replenished from elsewhere. Here, we can indeed generalize about the Hellenistic polis. Passing through the gymnasium or ephebate did not constitute an obligatory step toward citizenship or any other juridical status.Footnote 149

Scholarship has underestimated the extent to which the elite of the gymnasium disputed the egalitarian ethos of citizenship. One tends to recognize aristocratic origins, or emphasize a late turn toward elitism and exclusivity, while the sources themselves tell the story of an institution dominated in most periods and places by the few. Lykourgan Athens in this respect represents a notable exception. Consider that in Argos of the 420s, a select group of youths (logades) trained at public expense launched an oligarchic coup.Footnote 150 The Argos incident highlights the ever-present potential for conflict. These “disruptive neoi,” in Van Bremen’s apt formulation, stood in a different relationship to power from the rest of their community.Footnote 151 They looked to their heroes, to aristocrats, princes, and kings, for support, even when it discomfited or even enraged polis society. They were at once a threat to social cohesion and a vital connection to royal and later Roman authority. For the other citizens – including other elites – the task was to constrain the would-be aristocrats of the gymnasium, while still profiting from their ties to imperial power.

Ionian Metropolis, for example, honored Apollonios for his successful negotiation of fiscal and territorial disputes, but also for securing an oil fund from Attalos II “through his own persistence (διὰ τὴν ἰδίαν ἐκτένειαν)” (D5 Side B line 24).Footnote 152 The effort is private, but the good, we are assured, is public. In the civic discourse of the decree, Apollonios wins high repute in other cities and obviously the affection of Attalos, but never presses his own advantage at the expense of Metropolis and “the common good of the city” (τὰ κοινὰ τῆς πόλεως πράγματα) (Side B lines 16–17). Each of his actions manifests civic virtue, none more so than his death, which a second decree relates came leading the neaniskoi (armed youth of the gymnasium) against the rebel Aristonikos, “for the sake of his own virtue (arête) and that of his fatherland (patris)” (Side A line 37). This is the official image of Apollonios that the people of Metropolis have left us: a man of the court and of the gymnasium, firmly embedded in civic society. It is an image, however, that we cannot take at face value.Footnote 153 The city granted the sons of Apollonios the right to build a hero shrine (hêrôon) for his bones “before the city gate on their own property (πρὸ τῆς πύλης ἐν τοῖς ἰδίοις)” (Side A line 42). Jones sees Apollonios “as receiving true heroic honors from his city, even if the tomb is on private property.”Footnote 154 That the tomb is on private property does not make the honors any less heroic, only less civic. The tomb is outside the city’s enceinte. The city’s grant of approval is one last attempt to fix a larger-than-life benefactor in civic discourse.Footnote 155 Jones has also pointed out that Apollonios evinces a convergence of the public heroization of the Classical and Hellenistic periods with the private heroization of the period of the Roman Empire.Footnote 156 In death as in life, the Attalids’ friends in the city gymnasia walked a very thin line.

If we accept the rhetoric of these cities wholesale, the disjuncture between the elites of the gymnasium and civic society at large disappears. Yet that rift is the background to Attalid patronage of the gymnasium. In the case of Eirenias and Miletus, it deserves more attention. Eirenias, as we recall, was one of the ambassadors of the Ionian Koinon to Eumenes II in 167/6. They met on Delos, and Eumenes followed up with a letter to the Ionians the same year (RC 52). Sometime later, but before 164, Miletus honored its citizen Eirenias with a gilded statue on a very large, round base, which bears a decree (SEG XXXVI 1046).Footnote 157 The honorific decree for Eirenias informs us of the massive foundation of Eumenes II for the construction of a gymnasium: 160,000 medimnoi of wheat for sale, the proceeds of which were lent out at interest, and also sufficient wood for building. That wood was much needed. While Miletus had possessed at least two gymnasia since 206/5, it now began construction of a much larger complex with the new revenue and material. To give a sense of the scale, the palaistra of Eumenes’ gymnasium is estimated at ca. 7,000 m2, embarrassingly larger than the so-called Hellenistic Gymnasium endowed by Miletus’ own citizen Eudemos (1,600 m2).Footnote 158 Consensus places the so-called gymnasium of Eumenes II under a Roman bath in the city’s “Westmarkt Areal.” The unexcavated building relates to a slate of other structures that form a self-contained neighborhood. The gymnasium’s propylon aligns directly with the stadium to its east in an unusually axial orientation, implying an integrated plan.Footnote 159 A Milesian decree for Eumenes II was inscribed on one of the antae of the propylon (I.Milet 307), though whether the entire complex was completed in the king’s lifetime can be doubted.Footnote 160 In addition, the aligned, so-called Westmarkt is now seen to have consisted of running tracks, including a xystos. Finally, adjoining the running tracks is a peristyle known as the “Hofhaus am Athena-Tempel,” which is now interpreted as the possible temenos for the ruler cult of Eumenes II.

The decade-long involvement of Eirenias in the execution of such a monumental undertaking, which left its mark on an entire sector of the city of Miletus, produced a dossier of inscriptions. These have been ordered in relative sequence around fixed points like the letter of Eumenes II to the Ionians. Most of the documents illuminate the afterlife of the royal gift: the exceptional, full-blown ruler cult for a living Attalid that seems to have sprung up in response, then promises of further benefactions, then further embassies of Eirenias as representative of the Milesians. However, what interests us most here is the prehistory of the gymnasium’s foundation. While the honorific decree of the Milesians for Eirenias postdates the letter of Eumenes to the Ionians, the foundation mentioned in the decree for Eirenias predates the audience on Delos.Footnote 161 In other words, before he met Eumenes as an ambassador of the Ionians to deliver a koinon decree, or as a representative of Miletus bearing a civic decree, Eirenias approached the king in a private capacity, as an advocate of the gymnasium. According to Herrmann, this would represent the beginning of warm relations between Miletus and Pergamon.Footnote 162 The text reads: ἐντυχὼν δὲ καὶ βασιλεῖ Εὐμένει κατὰ τὴν δο|θεῖσαν ὑπὸ τοῦ πλήθους αὐτῶι συνχώρησιν καὶ διὰ τῆς ἰδίας συστάσεως|προτρεψάμενος αὐτὸν δοῦναι τῆι πόλει δωρεὰν (“He met with King Eumenes, according to the permission granted to him by the people, and, by means of his own good relations with the king, prevailed upon him to give the city the gift”) (SEG XXXVI 1046 Block I lines 4–6).

The point to stress is that the gift of the gymnasium of Eumenes II to Miletus came about through the initiative of one man, acting alone, but with the crucial permission of the Milesian assembly (plêthos).Footnote 163 In what sense did Eirenias need “permission”? For Herrmann, Eirenias sought a safeguard from the city.Footnote 164 To switch perspectives, might the city of Miletus not have wanted protection from Eirenias? The city, after all, later enshrined that detail of procedure in the decree, defining the gift in no uncertain terms as its own (dôrea têi polei). This is in contrast to a common formulation by which the recipient of royal patronage of the gymnasium is expressed as the members in the dative plural.Footnote 165 A great deal of money was at stake, and Eirenias would prove to have a hand in its administration until the end.Footnote 166 As we witnessed earlier, in the case of one King Ptolemy and the gymnasium of Halikarnassos, asking permission (synchôrêsis) was no pleasantry; it was a way of aligning interests. Yet one has typically seen the interests of Miletus and Eirenias aligned from the very beginning, the initial approach, and, therefore, explained the episode as simply the intervention of a leading citizen on behalf of his city.Footnote 167 There is no textual support for that reconstruction, only the familiar, banal, and suspicious statement that Eirenias always acted to the advantage of his polis and for the fame of his fatherland (Block I lines 2–4).

By the same token, one has wavered over the nature of another mission reported in the decree, which Eirenias made to the court of the Seleukid king Antiochos IV. Again, Eirenias traded on his rapport with a royal interlocutor, in this instance, the king’s sister-wife Laodike IV. The result was a grant of tax immunity to the People (demos) for certain goods (genêmata) exported from the region of the Milesia into the Seleukid kingdom. In the view of H. W. Pleket, Eirenias acted on behalf of Miletus, “or at least not without its consent,” though we are in fact given no indication either way.Footnote 168 Herrmann writes of diplomacy at Antioch, though Eirenias is not designated as presbeutês (ambassador), as he is elsewhere in the decree.Footnote 169 All we really know is that in retrospect, the city claimed the gift – for each and every citizen: πρὸς ἐπαύξησιν δὲ ἀνήκουσαν τῶν τε τῆς πόλεως καὶ τῶν ἑκάστου τῶν|ἰδιωτῶν προσόδων (“for the increase of the respective incomes of the city and of each individual”) (Block II lines 5–6).Footnote 170 It was just one more demonstration that Eirenias was a virtuous, model citizen (agathos politês) (Block II line 7).Footnote 171

In reality, Eirenias was not the model citizen. He was an extraordinary citizen and, therefore, worthy of extraordinary honors. Note that the round monument on which his decree was inscribed is suspiciously similar in form to the Ionian monument for Eumenes II – only bigger.Footnote 172 Yet the city’s treatment of Eirenias was not quite royal. Eumenes had been able to choose the site of his extraordinary monument: the temenos that Miletus had voted in his honor (RC 52 line 60).Footnote 173 By contrast, the siting of the monument for Eirenias was subject to a further decision (or vote?) of the demos, not left up to a board of magistrates or simply, as so often, designated loosely in the decree as “the most conspicuous spot” in the agora or gymnasium (SEG XXXVI 1046 Block II line 13). Unfortunately, we do not know where the monument stood, as its fragments were not found in situ.Footnote 174 But it is worth noticing that there was no role for the gymnasium crowd in the siting of the monument, while there had been one in the earlier case of Eudemos.Footnote 175 The demos had taken the decision out of their hands.

Again, for Miletus, Eirenias was a different kind of benefactor, which meant that he received unusual honors, but also unusual scrutiny. This is how we should understand the phrase “provided that the honor is confirmed in court (τῆς δὲ τιμῆς ἐπικυρωθείσης ἐν τῷ δικαστηρίῳ)” (Block II line 14). While Herrmann points out that such provisory ratification clauses, usually in a genitive absolute, are a common feature of Greek decrees, those that refer specifically to the confirmation of honors by a process of judicial review are much fewer in number.Footnote 176 We hear nowhere else of this Milesian dikastêrion, but parallels illuminate the spirit of the institutional arrangement. If assemblies tended to vote up or down on honorific decrees, the precise nature or size of the honor (timê) or “gift (dôrea)” of recompense might fall to others to decide.Footnote 177 This was a means of checking corruption, of legitimating each honor individually. As third-century Achaian Dyme insisted, the polis itself had judged each metic singly before awarding citizenship (κρίνασα καθ΄ ἕνα ἕκαστον) (Syll.3 529 lines 9–10). Herrmann also adduces as parallels grants of naturalization, which, along with the honor of isoteleia (tax equality for noncitizens), fourth-century Athens submitted to a process of review called dokimasia.Footnote 178 However, a more proximate phenomenon appears in Athens of the third century, which Gauthier has termed “dokimasia of rewards.”Footnote 179 Athens awarded outsized honors (megistai timai) to men who had played a decisive role in the city’s affairs on an international stage. One such man was the Athenian Phaidros of Sphettos, a major figure of influence in Ptolemaic Alexandria, who received a portfolio of honors just before 250 (IG II2 682).Footnote 180 A rider to the decree informs us that Phaidros had proposed his own honors in decree form, but that the gift (dôrea) was subject to the review (dokimasia) of a court (dikastêrion) (lines 92–101). Eirenias too may have had his own ideas about which honors he merited, but civic institutions existed to check him. This was the dynamic that structured relations between the gymnasium elite, their cities, and their Attalid patrons after 188. The gift itself was the end result of a negotiation on two levels: the city came to terms with the king, but also with its leading citizens.

The Gymnasium as an Association

Any insistence on friction and negotiation – on the gap or social distance between the gymnasium regulars and the rest – may still seem strained. We need to examine how the group organized and represented itself, how it took action. This was a voluntary association that straddled the divide between public and private. In fact, it was made up of several smaller groups called paides, epheboi, neoi, presbyteroi, and even apalaistroi, each with its own rules and habits.Footnote 181 Each group also possessed its own sense of corporate identity, but as institutions, their functions varied. In most cases, they all acted together, either passing a decree or partaking of the perquisites of belonging. Men and boys who frequented the gymnasium but did not belong to a subgroup, some probably noncitizens, seem to have been subsumed under the category of “those who belong to the gymnasium (οἱ μετέχοντες τοῦ γυμνασίου)” or “those who have use of the oil (οἱ ἀλειψαμένοι),” κτλ.Footnote 182 Moderns have struggled to define the umbrella grouping them all together.Footnote 183 In particular, the German tradition in legal history has taken up the problem, and German contains words like Vereinswesen and Verein that lack precise linguistic and cultural equivalents in the English language.Footnote 184 Scholars have also doubted whether the ancient names of the associations connoted juridical status.Footnote 185 For our purposes, it will suffice to think of the gymnasium as a kind of collective, but not one loosely organized by “weak ties” alone.Footnote 186 Members chose to participate, rather than find themselves automatically enrolled as citizens of a certain age class.Footnote 187 In fact, it must have been the strength of this collective as an institution that led many cities to impose a battery of officials on gymnasia – the civic gymnasiarch, his assistant the paidonomos, and the grammateus (secretary) – just when the power of the Attalids was peaking in mid-second-century Pergamon.Footnote 188 An institution this strong was liable to run its own line out to royal power, which is what happened in Termessos of 319, during the Wars of the Diadochoi, when the neoi picked a different dynast from their older peers.Footnote 189

The boldest and indeed most common expressions of the institutional identity of the gymnasium are its decrees. There are scores of inscriptions that emanate from a decision of the collective to honor its patron and publicize the act. It is easy enough to characterize these as harmless exercises in citizenship. What gives pause is the curious use of the procedure of prographê, whereby a gymnasium decree became a draft that the polis later decided to incorporate into a civic decree. We have reason to believe that this was a contentious process and that intergenerational or intra-elite conflict lurks behind our documents.Footnote 190 A case in point is Attalid Colophon. Prince Athenaios, the youngest son of Attalos I, seems to have endowed that city with a youths’ palaistra, perhaps already in the 180s when he was still a neos himself.Footnote 191 An inscription records honors for Athenaios (D10). The first editor of the text, Theodore Macridy, described it as an honorary decree for Athenaios, but as Gauthier made clear, the stone actually bears two decrees, the first providing for a statue of the prince in the sanctuary of Claros, the second for public sacrifice and games on his birthday.Footnote 192 The motivation clause for the second decree indicates that a certain collective of the gymnasium, perhaps “the regulars of the place” (οἱ μετέχοντες τοῦ τόπου), had already passed its own decree, or “pre-decree,” the aforementioned prographê. In it, the group honored Prince Athenaios as a benefactor: ψήφισ|[μα προεγράψαντο περὶ τοῦ] τιμῆσαι Ἀθήναιον ὄντα|[εὐεργέτην (lines 6–8). It is worth noting that the honors ratified in the second decree, the athletic events, are distinctly gymnasium-oriented, as is their administration, and even participation in the feast to follow: the gymnasiarch distributes the leftover meat to hoi aleipsamenoi (oil users), victors of past stephanephoric games, and various archons (lines 21–26). We catch a glimpse of the confrontational manner in which the neoi may have presented a gymnasium decree to the Council in an earlier civic decree of Colophon, which depicts a full 153 of them making one such submission.Footnote 193 Van Bremen adduces alongside these texts the vivid scene of the Pergamene neoi descending on the Council and Assembly of the royal capital en masse (κατὰ πλῆθος) in order to demand honors for the gymnasiarch Metrodoros (I.Pergamon 252 line 37).Footnote 194 As she points out, these are all cases of neoi, with all of youth’s potential for disruption, demanding that honors performed in the context of the gymnasium be promoted to citywide acclamation. These young men were not asking for permission to practice their citizenship in the simulation room of the gymnasium.Footnote 195

Intriguing evidence admits that the city did not dictate the circumstances under which the gymnasium passed its decrees, rendered its accounts, or appointed its magistrates. For example, the surviving fragment of the mid-second-century calendar of the gymnasium of Kos, attesting Ptolemaic, Cappadocian, but especially Attalid benefactions, speaks of a “council” (boulê), perhaps taking place in the sacred grove of Asklepios known as the Kypariss(i)on (D11 line 22). Unfortunately, whatever qualifier preceded the word boulê is gone.Footnote 196 Bringmann et al. hypothesize a meeting of instructors (Konferenz der Lehrer).Footnote 197 Edward Hicks had proposed a regular meeting of the Council of the polis of Kos, which representatives of the gymnasium were required to attend.Footnote 198 Yet much more likely is an occasion akin to the annual conclave in the gymnasium, termed synodos en tôi gymnasiôi, which the civic benefactor and Attalid courtier Kephisodoros required of the ephebes and paides of Apameia (D6 lines 15–16). Civic calendars do not seem to have had any bearing on the dates of these meetings. We even hear of the civic calendar of Iasos falling out of touch with the calendar of the city’s gymnasium. Herrmann has demonstrated that, at least in late Hellenistic or early Imperial times, the association used a different era than the city proper.Footnote 199

The organizational homologies between the gymnasium and polis institutions are undeniable. The various associations of the gymnasium imitate civic habits of record-keeping, honoring their benefactors, and publicity.Footnote 200 The question is whether, from an emic perspective, the gymnasium was ever an antagonist of the polis, or just the city writ small, as it is usually understood from our etic perspective. Indeed, already for Aristotle, the nonpolitical association (chrematistikê koinônia) had looked to the polis as its model.Footnote 201 For the philosopher, both groups aimed at the advantage (to sympheron) of their members. Yet surely, interests could and did diverge. The association of maritime traders in Aristotle’s treatment, for example, may have differed with their city’s port officials over the most advantageous way to organize harbor dues. Regarding the gymnasium and the city, these rival tendencies peaked in the second century BCE.Footnote 202 Witness what happened on Athenian Delos in 141/0. Up until then, the Athenian practice had been to elect the island’s gymnasiarch in the assembly in Athens. However, in that year, the electing body consisted of the Athenian governor (epimelêtes) and “those who frequent the gymnasium (οἱ ἀλειφομένοι)” (I.Delos 2580 lines 31–32). In the following year, the old practice was reinstituted for good – and spelled out ([χ]ει[ροτονη]θεὶς ὑπὸ τοῦ δήμου) (line 34). According to Christian Habicht, the reasons for this “messiness” are unclear.Footnote 203 Of course, ad hoc circumstances in Athens or on Delos may have led to this power play by the gymnasium’s regular membership. Yet as a lapse in a city’s control over a gymnasium, albeit one separated by a stretch of sea, it can be regarded as paradigmatic, rather than anomalous. In the absence of vigilance and pressure from the city, those who controlled the gymnasium were the elite, even the noncitizen population – which is to say, those who were present – and those who, like the king and his courtier, could with money make themselves present.Footnote 204

Close study of its architectural ensemble and place in urban plans of the period confirms the impression that the gymnasium restricted access in ways that must have served to exclude elements of the citizenry. In fact, it was only in Hellenistic times that the building complex of the gymnasium acquired a specific architectural typology. Above all, this included a large peristyle court, with rooms and exedrae forming a perimeter around a large central court. Architectural historians emphasize the integrity of the design: the gymnasium complex formed a closed architectural unity. The peristyle helped produce this effect, as did strong walls and built entryways, which eventually gained inviting propylaea. The unity of these complexes, often sited on slopes, made them at once key landmarks, glimpsed by all who approached the city or summoned its vista to mind, and also simple to close off – even from local outsiders. For all their iconicity, gymnasia were never as accessible as civic spaces like the Hellenistic theater or agora. In short, they were not open spaces. Of late, Ralf von den Hoff goes so far as to call their closure “hermetic.” In practice, it was much easier to see inside than to get inside, with propylaea serving as visual provocations: both barriers and windows. Moreover, pathways in and out of gymnasia do not communicate directly or even align along clean axes with public spaces like agorai. For example, from the agora of Sikyon, one can gaze directly up toward the terrace of a large Hellenistic gymnasium (Fig. 5.3). Yet one enters not from the east side facing the agora, but rather from a small, side gate on the north, which itself lacks direct communication with the theater it faces. Additionally, unlike most civic sanctuaries, gymnasia, which included shrines, tend to stand apart from processional routes.Footnote 205

Figure 5.3 Hellenistic Sikyon, view east/southeast from the terraces of the city’s gymnasium toward the adjacent agora.

(Sklifas Steven/Alamy Stock Photo)

At Pergamon, as noted, the Großes Gymnasion anchored the street plan of the East Slope of Eumenes’ city, marking a middle ground between the Old and New City. The terraced complex was highly visible, both from the plain below and beyond Eumenes’ walls, and along the axes of major streets that terminated at the structure’s two original gates. Indeed, the more impressive of the two gates, the western, contains a covered staircase, which is rotated toward alignment with the streets of the East Slope. Building on the work of Bielfeldt, Pirson singles out the Pergamene gymnasium as a rare and singularly monumental civic space in the royal capital.Footnote 206 Yet as these and other scholars have noted, the citizens of Pergamon remain invisible or anonymous in the epigraphy and archaeology of the gymnasium until the final years of the dynasty. Only under Attalos III did the demos begin to dedicate statues in the gymnasium and gymnasiarchs to receive honors.Footnote 207 The architecture itself conflicts with any straightforward characterization of Eumenes’ gymnasium as open to every citizen of Pergamon. On the contrary, access was tightly controlled (Fig. 5.1). One did not enter – as visitors do today – directly from the nearby sanctuaries of Demeter or Hera. Rather, the two original entryways, while set on the main thoroughfare of the city, were quite narrow and did not lead to the decorated Upper Gymnasium. Further, the entire complex of the gymnasium was enclosed, with walls on the east and west and a monumental retaining wall on the south. Late in the Hellenistic period, up-to-date bathing facilities were added to the complex. One entered these baths via the palaistra, which limited access to those already inside.Footnote 208 We may place this architectural closure in the context of a broader second-century pattern of creating self-contained ensembles in urban planning, segmenting the city according to function. However, the assumption that the Pergamene gymnasium restricted access because the institution it housed restricted access to citizens is unfounded.Footnote 209 Access was restricted, but neither limited nor guaranteed to the citizens. For those who belonged, this was a civic space, distinguished by the very absence of the kind of constraint that polis ideology typically placed on Hellenistic rulers. Visible but not transparent, the gymnasium belonged to the new collectivities on which the Attalid state was built.

New Collectivities

Among those who frequented the Delian gymnasium in the 140s were a sizable number of noncitizens.Footnote 210 Delos was especially cosmopolitan, but in this respect, it fits a pattern. As the Beroia law and a host of ephebic lists show, the Hellenistic gymnasium did not exclude noncitizens. In another illustrative case, from Eriza in Caria or from Phrygian Themisonion, a gymnasiarch named Chares was honored in 115/14 for providing oil to the “ephebes, neoi, and resident aliens.”Footnote 211 On the other hand, under the Attalids, it was not the gymnasium’s role to fully assimilate outsiders into the civic corps. If a noncitizen could access the gymnasium, once inside, he still retained his political status. The Attalids’ gymnasium did not so much produce new citizens as new collectivities, rooted in the realities of social life and Mediterranean mobility. The noncitizens of Mylasa – a colorful example – in a late Hellenistic decree of their own, honored Leontiades adoptive son of Philiskos, the gymnasiarch who at his own expense had provided them with 80 months’ worth of oil, which he made available all day and up until night. (Arbitrary closures, apparently, were common, at least for noncitizens.) In their short text, this group of subalterns twice emphasizes that as metics, paroikoi, and aliens, they lacked a share in the public oil distributed in the gymnasium. Yet with their dedication of a portrait statue of Leontiades, the group publicly memorialized their participation in a certain form of civic life.Footnote 212 Ultimately, the new collectivities of the gymnasium, these broader cross-sections of the Hellenistic polis, were the targets of the Attalids’ gifts. Indeed, the creation and the performance of the new collectivities owed much to royal sponsorship. So much so, in fact, that the Attalids’ constant care for the gymnasium cannot have been reflexive adherence to a static model of social organization in the polis. Rather, with imperial motives, the Attalids helped increase the formal participation of noncitizens in civic rituals, profiting from the enduring vitality of the polis as a source of identity, while also contributing to a radical overhaul of social relations.

We hear echoes of this process in documents that refer to limited distributions of consumable, which is to say, perishable goods to the typically broad-based gymnasium society: certainly oil, but also food, and perhaps sweet wine, too. These were events like the “royal banquets” of the gymnasium, the basilika deipna mentioned in the long decree of Colophon for Menippos (SEG XXXIX 1244 Column II line 47). We will return to them shortly, but it is enough to point out here that the Colophonians had hoped to reconstitute with civic monies a royal foundation for (annual?) banquets for neoi and presbyteroi. Publishing the inscription from Claros, the Roberts found a comparable institution in the endowment of Philetairos for the synagôgê (gathering) of the neoi in Kyzikos.Footnote 213 At such banquets, Attalid money convened a group in the gymnasium that almost certainly included noncitizens.

The protocols of the gymnasium banquet carried over the old status distinctions of the polis, but reorganized them according to a different logic, creating new symbolic frontiers between a select group of citizens, claiming aristocratic status, and the indistinct mass of other citizens.Footnote 214 Inside the gymnasium, it was presence itself, which trumped political rights exercised on the outside. The charters for the gymnasium feasts of Critilaos from Aigiale (Amorgos) and of Elpinikos from Eretria mandate different eating arrangements for citizens, metics, Romans, and temporary residents (parepidêmountes) – a larger piece of meat for the table of the ephebes. They do not, however, bar one from eating for lack of citizenship.Footnote 215 These two texts date to ca. 100, but already in the gymnasium honors that a certain Lydian city granted to Asklepides, courtier of Attalos II, a group of participants decidedly larger than the citizenry alone is envisioned.Footnote 216 To have a share in the distribution of the gymnasium banquet, it was more important to be present than to be a citizen. The new collective was not a virtual community. Its bonds were forged in real life. Thus, in the case of Critilaos, a share in the banquet goes to “those citizens who are present (τοῖς τε πολίταις τοῖς ἐπιδημοῦσιν),” just as it does to “those foreigners who are temporarily resident (ξένοις τοῖς παρεπιδημοῦσιν)” (lines 72–73). Gauthier underscores the point: this was a religious, not a civic festival, and one which demanded physical participation.Footnote 217 The basilika deipna of the gymnasium of Attalid Colophon would have been no different. For nowhere in the entire corpus of royal gifts to gymnasia is there a single instance of a distribution made exclusively to citizens in the manner of the grain fund of a Hellenistic polis. Habicht has restored one for the Gymnasium of Ptolemy in Athens, a conjecture that is worth reconsidering (IG II2 836).Footnote 218

On the contrary, the terms of at least one Attalid foundation, that of either Eumenes II or Attalos III for the gymnasium of Andros, imply a distribution in the manner of Critilaos and Aigiale: food for participation (D9). The honorific decree praises the gymnasiarch of Andros for having discharged his duties generously and lawfully, which in part meant organizing a procession and a feast on the king’s birthday. The gymnasiarch seems to have been generous in leading his own cow in procession, but indeed lawful in then sacrificing the animal immediately (παραχρῆμα) (line 8). The mandate to sacrifice immediately prevented the gymnasiarch from slaughtering the animal later, among different company.Footnote 219 It ensured that those who ate the meat were those who showed up on the king’s birthday, that the feast took place only in the gymnasium. At Aigiale, Critilaos showed the very same concerns for his feast: ἡ δὲ δημοθοινία γένεσθω ἐν τῷ γυμνασίῳ ἐπάναγκ̣ες (“the banquet absolutely must take place in the gymnasium”) (lines 59–60). And the flowers, the sacrificial victims, along with their skins – they were all to be consumed “immediately,” again, παραχρῆμα (line 62). Both rituals incorporate elements of civic ideology. For example, at Aigiale, the procession begins at the city’s prytaneion, while on Andros, a sacrifice is made on behalf of the demos. Yet in each case, the focus of the ritual is squarely on the patron of the gymnasium and his family: Critilaos and his prematurely deceased, heroized son Aleximachos, or the king, his father, and their queens.

We may now return to the issues raised in the case of Colophon and Menippos. Not long after the War of Aristonikos, the Colophonians had voted to revive so-called royal banquets. The city assumed control and financial responsibility for an Attalid institution. However, sufficient public money did not materialize, and the city resorted to the appointment of magistrate-liturgists called epimênioi to make up the difference. Menippos then intervened to release both the city and any would-be elite peers of the entire financial burden. The city had suffered greatly in a war that ushered in a profound change of the social fabric of the region’s poleis. After Aristonikos, we see fully, on the one hand, the emergence of peerless super-citizens and, on the other, the erosion of distinctions between ordinary citizens and noncitizen permanent residents. Leading citizens like Menippos, but also Polemaios of Colophon, and Moschion of Priene, instituted public feasts that created the new collectivities that crisis seemed to demand.Footnote 220 As Fröhlich observes, these feasts were at once a gathering of the entire population and also a means of distinguishing elite groups, which is to say, of maintaining – if reorganizing – the status distinctions of the polis.Footnote 221 As heirs to the kings’ legacy and ex-ephebes themselves, the outsized civic benefactors of the period knew the gymnasium as the civic institution in which presence counted the most, in which the role one played was the youth, the king, the hero, Alexander or Herakles, and not the middling citizen. The “royal banquets” of the gymnasium, then, were the perfect model for the new “inclusive” public feasts. Menippos, who as a mere neos, according to his epigraphical biography, proved his worth to Colophon on embassies to the Attalid kingdom (Attalikê basileia), was responsible for reconstituting the kings’ feasts. Yet he was also credited with sponsoring a lavish public feast (dêmothoina) during the Epiphany of Dionysus that fed citizens on the first day, and metics and holders of isoteleia on the second.Footnote 222 These men literally towered above their co-citizens: life-size portrait statues of Polemaios and Menippos stood on columns over 9 m tall in the Sanctuary of Apollo at Claros. The monument of Menippos, on which his decree was inscribed, squeezed itself between a statue of Antiochos IV and the Temple of Apollo itself.Footnote 223 The social distance between Menippos and the other Colophonians recalled the gulf between the kings and the rest. And like the kings, they found in the gymnasium a civic space that conformed to the realities of power and demography.

As we read in the roughly contemporary Colophonian decree for Polemaios, the War of Aristonikos had sent refugees pouring into the city.Footnote 224 Polemaios helped provide for the outsiders, and seems to have promoted the idea of a public subscription (epidosis) for their welfare. At his wedding, he treated citizens to a sweet wine distribution called glykismos, while to noncitizens he gave a portion of meat. The wedding of Polemaios, just like the public feast of Menippos, was an occasion for the ritual performance of a new collectivity in Colophon. In this respect, these rituals mimicked long-standing practice in the gymnasium, an institution with which both men were familiar.Footnote 225 Indeed, in Pergamon itself and elsewhere in the region, post-Attalid elites soon began using the rituals of the gymnasium to integrate outsiders.Footnote 226 The long decree of Sestos in honor of Menas, former Attalid stratêgos of the Chersonnese and the Thracian topoi, priest of King Attalos in his city, and twice gymnasiarch, provides a wealth of detail.Footnote 227 During Menas’ second stint as gymnasiarch, post-Attalid Sestos was in dire circumstances, with the raids of nearby Thracians preventing the cultivation of its territory. In this case, the integration of outsiders was vital for the survival of the city. Menas consecrated his inaugural Hermaia kai Herakleia festival “for the salvation of the demos and the neoi,” and “he invited to the sacrifice not only those who have a share of the oil, but everyone else as well, even giving a share to foreigners (ἐκάλεσεν ἐπὶ τὰ ἱερὰ οὐ μόνον τοὺς μετέχοντας τοῦ ἀλείμματος|ἀλλὰ καὶ τοὺς λοιποὺς πάντας ποιούμενος τὴν μετάδοσιν τῶν ἱερῶν καὶ τοῖς ξέ|νοις)” (lines 60–67).

We have lingered over the historical context of the decree of Colophon for Menippos because the novelties of civic life in the sub-Hellenistic world refract earlier interventions by kings. It has long been recognized that a veritable cult of civic benefactors in the first century BCE was modeled on Hellenistic ruler cult. Yet it also pays bearing notice that the Attalid kings, in effect, piloted the expansion of participation in civic rituals that we tend to associate with the chaos and rapid social change that transpired after their demise. The choice of the gymnasium as the quintessential beneficiary of Pergamene redistribution meant that participation of noncitizens in a steeply hierarchical political community was normalized within its walls. Outside, civic intellectuals were just then debating the ethics of an unbridled philanthropy that reduced co-citizens to clients and blurred boundaries with outsiders.Footnote 228 The logic of the “inclusive” public feasts of the sub-Hellenistic period and the earlier basilika deipna of the gymnasium was the same, namely, the creation of a new collectivity that transformed the status distinctions of the polis without breaking them. The polis remained a powerful source of identity, but the meaning of citizenship and participation in civic life had changed forever. From the Andros inscription, we can discern the logic of an Attalid-sponsored public banquet in the polis (D9). For the processions that led up the feasts, two texts suggest similarly broad participation.Footnote 229 On Kos, ca. 180, Ariarathes IV celebrated military success with a procession that entailed the participation of the gymnasiarch, the neoi, and the ephebes, and he promised to crown three groups: citizens, paroikoi, and temporary residents of Kos (SEG XXXIII 675, lines 6–7). The Attalids were very active patrons of the gymnasium of Kos in this period and very close allies of Ariarathes IV.Footnote 230 We may imagine that Attalid festivals on Kos were similarly organized. Moreover, we know much of the procession that welcomed the victorious Attalos III home to Pergamon (OGIS 332 lines 33–38). It included the priesthood and the magistrates of the city of Pergamon, but also its ephebes and neoi, gymnasiarch, paides and paidonomos, and finally the citizens, their wives and daughters, as well as the other inhabitants (enoikountes).

The aim here was to provide a framework of explanation for the Attalids’ habit of funding gymnasia in cities under their control or influence. Scholars have taken the benefits of the arrangement to be self-evident. On this reckoning, the Attalids gave to the gymnasium in order to produce loyal subjects or, in slightly less Machiavellian terms, out of an ill-defined Panhellenism.Footnote 231 As for the cities, the last wave of work on the Hellenistic polis argues that the vitality of civic institutions after Chaironeia left the Attalids with little choice; the cities imposed this model of giving on the kings, further strengthening polis identity in the face of royal power. Behind these explanations lies a pair of related assumptions about the true beneficiary of the arrangement, and so about who initiated it. Yet both sides had something to gain, and, usually, we cannot know who pushed first. Taking a fresh look at the exchange brings out the true nature of the sovereignty play. Attalid patronage of the gymnasium strengthened polis identity, but it weakened popular control of communal self-representation before royal power. An elite group, theoretically open to noncitizens, now negotiated directly with Pergamon over a city’s fate. Those who had a share of the oil also had access to the king, who now had a bridgehead into civic life, precisely what Apollonidas of Sikyon was trying to prevent by blocking the gift of Eumenes II to the Council of the Achaean Koinon. Correspondingly, we can now better sense the full sting of the sovereignty violation of Sulpicius, the Roman who entertained complaints against the Attalids from a seat in the gymnasium of Sardis.

In the mid-second century, the gymnasium was not “the city writ small,” but rather, the preferred site of interaction between cities and kings. Eumenes II, who made an architectural spectacle out of one, unparalleled in its size and spatial complexity, the singular visual reference point for his new capital city, helped focalize civic life into its confines. He helped further politicize the gymnasium, and eventually, after the Attalids were gone, it emerged as a “second agora,” in which the city’s heroized dead were buried and the collective voice of the free inhabitants routinely expressed. Under the Attalids, what facilitated the rise of the gymnasium, it has been argued, were the dynamics of the institution at this juncture in its historical development, such as its peculiar system of finance, or the seemingly endless opportunities for embellishment it offered its patrons. The gymnasium also offered members of this dynasty, ever the financial sophisticates capable of exploiting the anonymizing power of money, a way to launder money to their supporters. We must also be aware that the Attalids faced an institution in flux, and that the intensity of their benefactions must have affected or exploited the following processes. Curty has written of a mid-second-century transitional period in the evolution of the gymnasiarchy, which saw the gymnasiarch take over the oil supply, just as the city began to take charge of honoring the gymnasiarch. The mid-second century also witnessed a race to amass social capital in the gymnasium, in evidence with the formal appearance of the gymnasium’s presbyteroi as an association. The Attalids participated in and stood to profit from any struggle over the definition of the gymnasium as a public space. They certainly contributed to increasing its profile, as the monumental, marble architecture of the gymnasium now begins to turn up in the archaeological record.Footnote 232

This chapter was also an essay on the distinctive nature of the gymnasium as a civic institution. If this was the preferred site of interaction with royal power, what might that say about its relation to other civic institutions? The gymnasium enjoyed a measure of autonomy from those other civic institutions, it was argued, and occupied a unique position vis-à-vis king and court. Ironically, this fact has become obscure to us precisely because both parties – the kings and the cities – wanted it to be so. At every turn, cities sought to constrain the elites of their gymnasia and bind them ideologically to the polis. As for the Attalids, they certainly intended their patronage of the gymnasium to be perceived as gifts to “Greek cities (poleis Hellênidas)” in the terms of Polybius (32.8.5). A final example comes from Chios, where an inscription records two gifts of “Attalos,” one for the renovation of the city’s walls, and a second for the heating of the gymnasium.Footnote 233 One struggles to relate these gifts chronologically to the voluntary subscription (epidosis) of Chios for wall construction, particularly because the Attalid text also lists the names and properties of locals.Footnote 234 Yet in epigraphic terms, the association of the two public goods, sturdy walls and a gymnasium, could not have been any tighter. We lack an explicit statement of the Chians on what the gymnasium meant to them, but the epidosis document provides stark testimony for the walls: the freedom (eleutheria) and autonomy (autonomia) of the homeland (patris) (lines 1–2). If the Attalids had convinced at least some of the Chians to think similarly of the gymnasium, they had achieved success.

Footnotes

1 ἅτε παρεστηκὼς ἄνθρωπος τῇ διανοίᾳ καὶ φιλοδοξῶν ἐν τῇ πρὸς Εὐμένην διαφορᾷ.

2 For the wider historical context, see Hansen Reference Hansen1971, 125.

3 See, e.g., Walbank 1957–79, vol. 3, 471.

4 Tralles, with its secondary Attalid palace, seems to have supplanted Sardis in the administrative hierarchy. See Savalli-Lestrade 2001, 82–86. As for Sardis, the current state of archaeological knowledge of Hellenistic Sardis is presented by articles in Berlin and Kosmin Reference Berlin, Kosmin, Berlin and Kosmin2019. (For earlier ideas, see Capdetrey 2007, 369–71; Ratté 2008.) Of note is the hypothesis that Antiochos I – not Attalos I, ca. 226/5 – was responsible for the poliadization of Sardis, making the second quarter of the third century decisive, in terms of both public, architectural change and private, material, cultural change at the domestic level. Frustratingly little is known of the Seleukid city plan, and Stinson (Reference Stinson, Berlin and Kosmin2019, 140) is rightly cautious, writing of “at least a gymnasium … and a theater” by the late third century, while Berlin and Kosmin (Reference Berlin, Kosmin, Berlin and Kosmin2019, 238) add a stoa with shops in what they call the new, civic-oriented middle city. Cf. doubts of Kaye 2016, 553–56. The Attalid downgrade of Sardis in favor of Tralles completes a shift, already under way, by which the Royal Road ceded prominence to the Common Road (Kosmin Reference Kosmin2019, 88–89) and, I would add, to the Maeander Corridor. Ultimately, an Anatolian imperial geography replaced a Near Eastern one. The new stratigraphy of the theater of Sardis presents a caveat to the hypothesis of an Attalid turn away from Sardis. A first phase belongs to the second quarter of the third century; a second, the first theater in stone, ca. 175–150. Despite its scale and monumentality, on the same plan as the later Roman theater, seating ca. 10,000, it seems hazardous to assign the theater to Eumenes II, as Berlin (Reference Berlin, Berlin and Kosmin2019, 66–67). Indeed, Ladstätter argues (2016, 262–65; 2019, 204) that Ephesus received its first stone theater with its lavish stage building in the very same period, i.e., under Eumenes II. Yet why the Attalids – who are not known as theater builders – deserve the credit, is unclear.

5 Gauthier 1989, 37–38.

6 For a digest of earlier scholarship, see Schmidt-Dounas Reference Schmidt-Dounas2000, 52–61. For “those who frequent the gymnasium” and the various locutions of corporate identity, see Gauthier 2006, 481. Generally, on the Hellenistic gymnasium and ephebate, A. Chankowski Reference Chankowski, Fröhlich and Müller2010 (for the Greek cities of the Aegean and Asia Minor) and the catalogue of Kennell Reference Kennell2006 are fundamental.

7 For the ephebes of Jerusalem, see Honigman Reference Honigman2014, 199–214.

8 Panathenaia kai Eumeneia: OGIS 305; for recent comment on this festival, see Jones 2000, 5.

9 Cf. the skepticism of Gruen 1984, 127, 181.

10 See already Robert 1937, 84–85, for a list of Attalid gifts with special attention paid to the gymnasium. Stappmanns (Reference Mann2012, 247) casts the gymnasium of Pergamon as a gift from Eumenes II to the citizens of Pergamon.

11 Cf. Marcellesi 2004, 173, on royal benefaction at Miletus: “Il n’y a guère de différence entre l’évergétisme séleucide et l’évergétisme lagide ou attalide dans la nature de dons.” Of course the political imperatives had changed, but the focus of benefaction did too.

12 The omission of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 88 [E], from the list of gymnasium foundations in the synthesis of Schmidt-Dounas (Reference Schmidt-Dounas2000, 55) seems to be a mistake, as does the omission of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 83 [E], Demetrios Poliorcetes’ dedication of “Rhodian spoils” as an oil fund in Thebes.

13 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 88 [E], for which a date of ca. 270–263 is given. Cf. Philetairos’ oil fund in Kyzikos (Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 241 [E]).

14 Gauthier 2006 = D10.

15 The Toriaion dossier was published after Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, but it is discussed in a companion volume. See Bringmann Reference Bringmann2000, 142.

16 The partitive genitive must refer back to a revenue source, from the context, likely land, which is again earmarked for an oil fund. Potentially, RC 51 may support or vitiate the arguments laid out in what follows. The problem is that the community addressed is not identified in the surviving text. Thus we cannot determine if it is a katoikia or a polis. A polis is mentioned in line 14, but Welles takes it to be Pergamon itself, where some of the cleruchs will be quartered. In the case of Toriaion (D8), we can observe the transformation of the katoikia into a polis. There, it is a matter of debate whether the earlier katoikia possessed a gymnasium, which is then officially recognized, or whether the creation of the gymnasium signals the creation of the polis. My view, argued infra, is that the gymnasium is a feature of the Hellenistic polis, but not a sine qua non. Moreover, evidence from Ptolemaic Thera shows that a garrison community might attract royal patronage for its gymnasium and interact with royal power on this score just as any polis would (IG XII 3 327 + p. 283). Fröhlich (2009, 62 n. 26) analyzes the Theran document alongside the corpus of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995. See now a possible gymnasium at the Seleukid garrison town of Jebel Khalid on the Euphrates (Area C; Clarke Reference Clarke, Clarke, Jackson, Nixon, Tidmarsh, Wesselingh and Cougle-Jose2016).

17 Ed. pr. of the text: Malay Reference Ma1999, no. 182; cf. text and commentary of SEG XLIX 1540, esp. for question of authorship; Aneziri and Damaskos Reference Aneziri, Damaskos, Kah and Scholz2004, 259 n. 89. For the identity of Asklepides and further speculation on authorship, see SEG LIII 1342 and Thonemann 2008, 50.

18 See Kaye and Souza Reference Kaye and Souza2013. Apollonia-on-the-Maeander: Petzl 2001, 56; Thonemann 2003, 100–102. Cf. Patrice Hamon BE (2014) no. 426.

19 For earlier research, see Radt 1999, 113–34.

20 For gymnasium and urban plan of Pergamon, see Stappmanns Reference Mann2012. On attribution to Eumenes II, see also Pirson 2012, 215.

21 Hoff 2004, 384.

22 Mathys et al. 2012, 271.

23 Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 251–52. Ca. 10,000–15,000 m2 seems to be the norm. Only the gymnasia of Messene and of the sanctuary of Olympia reach the same proportions. See also on these figures, Trümper Reference Trümper, Matthaei and Zimmermann2015, 173 n. 24.

24 Pirson 2012, 215–16. For the earlier street plan, see Wulf-Rheidt Reference Wulf-Rheidt1994.

25 The results of recent test trenches and ceramic analysis have changed the chronology of the Lower Agora. It is now believed to be a post-Attalid monument of the first century BCE and first century CE. See Pirson 2014b, 129–31; Pirson Reference Pirson, Ateş, Bartz, Brückner, Feuser, Mania, Meier, Seeliger, Matthaei and Zimmermann2015, 122–26.

26 Wörrle 2007; Bielfeldt 2010.

27 Radt 1999, 115; Mathys et al. 2012, 271. Also of relevance here is the problem of the date of the main temple in the gymnasium of Pergamon, likely that of Asklepios. The orientation of the Ionic temple fits with the rest of the complex. However, the building contains pieces of an older Doric building. These have been tentatively attributed to the (yet-to-be-discovered) extra-mural Nikephorion, which was destroyed by Philip V in 201. See Radt 1999, 131.

28 See Paul Jacobstahl in MDAI(A) 33 (1908), 381–83,3, with corrections of Hugo Hepding in MDAI(A) 35 (1910), 419.

29 Wörrle 2007, 215: “eine Art joint venture von König und Demos.”

30 Syll.3 671 = I.Tralleis 107; Strabo 12.8.18.

31 For the Roman bath–gymnasium phenomenon in Asia Minor and its physical relationship to the Hellenistic gymnasium, see Yegül Reference Yegül2010, 154–80, esp. 155–57. On Roman administrative centers built on top of Hellenistic gymnasia, see further Burkhalter Reference Burkhalter1992. For the modern obstacles to excavation at Tralles, see Dinç Reference Dinç2003, 4. Dinç notes a first-century BCE predecessor to the bath–gymnasium complex, destroyed in the earthquake of 26 (p. 33). However, the claim is also made that Apatourios of Alabanda built a gymnasium in Tralles (p. 4). This figure, known only from Vitr. De arch. 7.5.5, is in fact believed to have been active in the second century BCE – see Howe et al. Reference Howe, Rowland and Dewar1999, 268. But Vitruvius mentions only Apatourios’ ekklêsiastêrion at Tralles, not, as Dinç writes, a theater and a gymnasium (p. 4). More recent excavations have focused on the western necropolis. For discussion, see Saraçoğlu Reference Saraçoğlu2011. Note the lack of Classical or Hellenistic remains in Ateşlier Reference Ateşlier and Özdem2015.

32 Polyb. 21.46.10; Plin. HN 35.72; Vitr. De arch. 2.8.9.

33 SEG XLVI 1434.

35 Knibbe 1964–65, 1–6; for important emendations of this text, see also Jean and Louis Robert BE (1968) no. 464; see also Engelmann Reference Engelmann1975; Herrmann 1976, 233–34.

36 See Savalli-Lestrade 2005, 15 n. 18; Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 260.

37 See Veyne Reference Veyne1976, 228–30.

38 Robert 1960, 124–25: “cet édifice caractéristique de la culture grecque … le lieu par élection où se manifestait le culte royal avec le loyalisme envers les souverains hellénistiques.” For the manufacture of loyal subjects, see also Gauthier 1989, 93.

39 Dreyer 2004, 218: “wollten durch den frühen Einfluß auf Kinder und Jugendliche neue Loyalitätsbindungen schaffen und sich den erwachsenen Bürgern als Wohltäter und Förderer hellenischer Kultur empfehlen.” See also Schmidt-Dounas (Reference Schmidt-Dounas2000, 60), for whom the gymnasium guarantees the continuity of Greek culture, and the Attalids, as the supreme patrons of Greek culture, are the natural benefactors of the gymnasium.

40 Arist. Pol. 1321b.

41 Pausanias 10.4.1.

42 Gruen 2000; Schalles Reference Schalles1985.

43 L. Mitchell Reference Mitchell2007, xviii.

44 L. Mitchell Reference Mitchell2007, 208. For the complicated question of the date of Chremonides’ decree, see SEG LVI 190.

45 For Attalid visual rhetoric, see Stewart 2004, 228–32; Seaman Reference Seaman and Miles2016.

46 Cf. Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 313 [E], an honorific decree of Delphi for Eumenes II, which mentions both his tireless effort on behalf of “Hellenes” and his many gifts to “Greek cities”; and cf. RC 52 where Eumenes represents himself, in accordance, it seems, with the Ionians’ own claim, as (1) benefactor of “all Hellenes,” (2) defender of these Hellenes against barbarians, and (3) benefactor for the welfare of “those inhabiting Greek cities” (lines 8–12); finally, cf. Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 49 [E], from Kalauria, documenting a benefaction of Eumenes II to Poseidon, the polis, and “the other Hellenes.” I do not argue that a chauvinistic Pergamene Panhellenism did not exist, only that it does not adequately explain the dynasty’s intensive involvement with the gymnasium.

47 On portrait statues of the Attalids in gymnasia throughout the kingdom, see Hoff 2018, 264. Notably, these were not necessarily all cult statues.

48 For neaniskos as essentially a technical term, referring to the “neos at arms,” see Bremen Reference Bremen2013, 35.

49 I.Metropolis 1 = D5. For a possible Attalid-trained ephebic artillery force at Metropolis, see Aybek and Dreyer 2011, 213. In general, Ionia in the 180s witnessed widespread inter-polis warfare without royal interference. See Ager 2007; Ma 2000, 350–51.

50 The polis of the Tabênoi, addressed in a royal letter (SEG LVII 1109), has not been identified. The stone was found near Phrygian Hierapolis (Pamukkale), which fits with the mention of Apameia. Yet if the addressee were Carian Tabai, the stone would need to be considered a pierre errante. The ed. pr. is Guizzi Reference Guizzi2006. Guizzi translates neaniskoi tôn oikeiôn, “giovani dei ‘familiari,’” while Thonemann (2013b, 16) terms the group the “wider clan” of Koteies. See also Ritti et al. Reference Ritti, Hüseyin Baysal, Miranda, Guizzi and Fırat2008, no. 3. Further on the episode, see Thonemann 2013b, 15–16; Ma 2013a, 60 n. 44 on the identity of the addressee.

51 Patrice Hamon BE (2009) no. 440.

52 A. Chankowski 2009, 98–103.

54 A. Chankowski 2009, 101: “Il s’agit donc d’une pratique administrative récurrente.”

55 SEG XXXIX 1283 and 1285. On the antiquity of the arrangement in Herakleia, I am agnostic. I am unwilling to take these cities at their word when they claim to have held a privilege “ex archês.”

56 A. Chankowski 2009, 114: “l’incapacité des souverains à s’appuyer sur une autre modèle que celui de la cité, et la vitalité des institutions de la cité qui diffusent dans différentes régions du monde grec les mêmes modèles socio-culturels … la popularité du modèle civique du gymnase justifie à elle seule son instauration” (emphasis added). Similarly, Daubner 2015, 40: “We should not assume that this connection reveals much about the relationship of the ruler to the gymnasium or any particular interest in this institution on his part, but it is important for his relation to the polis.”

57 See Bringmann 2004 for the process by which a new polis might adopt the institution of the gymnasium.

58 On the chronological spread of the evidence and the resultant historiographical difficulties, see A. Chankowski Reference Chankowski, Fröhlich and Müller2010, 435.

59 On the historiographical challenge, see Ma Reference Ma1999, 1.

60 Migeotte 1984, no. 101 lines 10–13.

61 Migeotte 1984, no. 102.

62 Migeotte (1984, 318–19) also offers more nuanced translations of “synchôrein.” Similarly, Hamon (2009, 357 n. 18) prefers the French “concession” for synchôresis in the decree for Eirenias (SEG XXXVI 1046 Block I lines 4–6). In any case, if Ptolemy did provide funds to Halikarnassos, and the subscription was only meant to cover a shortfall, as Migeotte speculates, this text would need to be added to the corpus of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995.

63 For Lykourgan Athens and the precipitous drop in ephebic participation in the following century and a half, see Oliver Reference Oliver2007, 175–76; Perrin-Saminadayar Reference Perrin-Saminadayar2007, 63–86. For the dramatic change in the siting of the gymnasium, which took place during the Classical period, see Delorme Reference Delorme1960, 442–43. On the various locations for the gymnasium in the Hellenistic city, see Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 252–54.

64 Kennell Reference Kennell2006 (A Register of Greek Cities with Citizen Training Systems), esp. xii for the chronological peak of 65 cities with an ephebate in the second century BCE.

65 For periodization, see Thonemann 2016, 8: “[T]he modern historiography of the later Hellenistic period is, frankly, a bit of a mess.” For Hamon (Reference Hamon, Fröhlich and Müller2009, 377–79), the historical rupture that marks the basse époque héllenistique eludes explanation on the present state of the evidence. On the “second agora”: Robert, OMS II, 812–14, esp. 814 n. 3; VI, 422–23. On public burial in the late Hellenistic gymnasium, see Chiricat Reference Chiricat, Fröhlich and Müller2005; Bremen Reference Bremen2013, 39; cf. Kaye and Souza Reference Kaye and Souza2013, 99. Such burials are crucial evidence for the transformation of the gymnasium into a “second agora,” with towering benefactors honored as founder-heroes in a newly politicized space. However, a reexamination of the posthumous honors for the Pergamene courtier Asklepides (SEG XLIX 1540) confirms the standard chronology: this is a development that seems to postdate the collapse of the Attalid kingdom.

66 For a distinctive Attalid relationship to civic elites, see Kertész Reference Kertész1992; Dreyer Reference Dreyer, Kah and Scholz2009; but also Polyb. 32.8.5.

67 Bringmann et al. 1995, no. 106 [E]; see Habicht 1983 for the identification of the other donors as “true” Lariseans, and not Philip’s Macedonian settlers. This text tells against Macedonian exceptionalism.

68 Cf. Hatzopoulos 2001: “Macedonian Palaces: Where King and City Meet.”

69 For discussion, see Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 68 [L]. Note that, for Diodorus, the ambassadors approach the synodos.

71 Ascertaining the economic condition of Rhodes after Pydna and the Roman punitive action regarding the tax status of Delos is a historical problem, as this passage from Polybius suggests.

72 Walbank 1957–79, vol. 3, 515.

74 For the eranos-loan, see Millett Reference Millett1991, 152–59.

75 Cf. Eckstein Reference Eckstein and Balot2009, 259.

76 For the problem of defining demokratia in the epigraphy of the Hellenistic city and in royal chancery language, see Rhodes and Lewis Reference Rhodes and Lewis1997, 528–64, esp. 533–34; and the epigraphical register of Carlsson Reference Carlsson2010, 334–43. For aristocratic kalokagathia and the Hellenistic gymnasium, see Gehrke 2004, 415.

78 Gauthier 1995, 7.

79 Gehrke (2004, 414) is agnostic.

80 Gauthier 1995, 8; Gauthier 1980, 212.

81 Xanthos and Lyson (SEG XLVI 1721): Gauthier 1996; Colophon: Gauthier 2006; prolegomenon: Gauthier 1995.

82 Dreyer 2004, 234: “Der Verbindung zwischen den Neoi und den Demos war demnach unauflöslich; die Neoi waren in ihren verschiedenen, hier umrissenen Aggregat-zuständen ein Abbild der gesamten Bürgerschaft.”

83 Gehrke 2004, 416: “In der körperlich-geistigen Formierung sowie in Ritual und Ausstatung wurde mithin fassbar und sichtbar, wie eng das Gymnasion mit der Identität der Polis verbunden war.”

84 Kennell Reference Kennell2006, vii. Despite its title, that corpus seems to register the totality of gymnasium society, not just ephebes. See, further, Kennell 2015, on the ephebeia’s function to produce citizen-warriors. See also Habicht 1983, 31–32 (on Larisa): “Bau und Unterhaltung einer solchen, der Erziehung der Jugend gewidmeten Anlage war natürlicherweise eine Sache der Bürgerschaft und wurde in Larisa, wie dies auch für viele andere Städte bezeugt ist, selbstverständlich so angesehen” (emphasis added).

85 Bremen Reference Bremen2013, 47. Cf. Gehrke 2004, the essay entitled, “Eine Bilanz: Die Entwicklung des Gymnasions zur Institution der Sozalisierung in der Polis,” which puzzlingly makes no mention of kings.

86 Strabo 12.4.7.

88 On generalization, see the reflections of Gauthier 1995, 9; Gehrke 2004, 414.

89 IG XIV 422; see Schuler 2004a, 180–81 for problem of date (second or first century BCE) and discussion.

90 Roussel Reference Roussel1916, 189.

91 For discussion, see Migeotte Reference Migeotte2009.

92 Schuler 2004a, 180. For shortfalls in late Hellenistic public finance, see, e.g., Hegelochos’ bailout of Kyaneai: SEG LVI 1721. It is worth noting that political scientists can point to the surprising power of weak institutions to determine resource allocation in favor of interest groups, e.g., on Zimbabwe, Herbst 1990.

93 SEG XLIII 381 (esp. Side A lines 13–16); I.Iasos 23.

94 I.Iasos 23 lines 15–17.

95 For these standards, see Fröhlich 2004a.

96 On “Mischfinanzierung” and disorder (“Unregelmässigkeit”), see Schuler 2004a, 179, 185. Similarly, Moretti 1982, 56: “Ma in età ellenistica il carattere aleatorio, eventuale, del contributo pubblico impone il ricorso ad alter forme di finanziamento.” Finally, Delorme 1960, 456: “les fonds proviennent constamment de ressources occasionnelles.”

98 Habicht 1976. On the text, see A. Chankowski Reference Chankowski, Fröhlich and Müller2010, 38 n. 85.

99 Habicht (1976, 191) conjectures that the funding gap came in some phase of the First Macedonian War, in other words, the late third century.

100 Column B line 7. See further the case of Priene in the early first century BCE. The benefactor Zosimos reinstituted the association of the neoi after a hiatus (I.Priene 114 lines 17–19).

101 Curty Reference Curty2015, 278. Adaios of Amphipolis: SEG XLIII 371.

102 See Schuler 2004a, 187 n. 147. It was often the case that the gymnasium received an annual subvention from the polis, which normally made up only part of an operating budget, while the gymnasiarch added a personal contribution.

103 Generally considered a late Hellenistic phenomenon, but see Schuler 2004a, 183, for earlier cases of the “Spartan reality” behind the luxury of the honorific decrees.

104 Schuler 2004a, 185–86.

105 For the family of merchants to which Leonidas belonged, see Miller Reference Miller1974.

106 For the hemiolios, see Müller 2005.

107 For the gymnasiarchikon, see Migeotte 2000, 153, noting its obscurity; we hear of it only when gymnasiarchs substituted their own money in its place and were duly honored.

108 IG XII 3 327. For discussion, see Migeotte 2013, 117–18.

109 Adak and Stauner Reference Adak and Stauner2018, 5–7.

110 Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993 = SEG XLIII 381. For a date pre-168/7, see Hatzopoulos 1996, vol. 1, 137–38.

111 Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 51.

112 For extestai as civic magistrates, see Fröhlich 2004a, 117–68.

113 This is demonstrated grammatically either by use of a genitive of possession or by a participle of the verb ὑπάρχειν with a dative of possession.

114 For kyrieia as possession, see Chaniotis Reference Chaniotis, Harris and Rubinstein2004, 186.

115 Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 127–28: “En ce sens, ‘les neoi,’ groupe par définition mouvant et hétérogene (citoyens et étrangers), continuent à former, après l’adoption de la loi, une entité, que tout à la fois reconnaît et contrôle.”

116 Moretti (Reference Moretti1982, 56–57) underlines that the expression koinai prosodoi elsewhere refers to gymnasiaum patrimony; Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 124–28, 140 (insisting on the point); Fröhlich 2004a, 380.

117 Similarly, the aphêgoumenos of Side B lines 2–5 is an appointee of the gymnasiarch, a kind of hypogymnasiarchos and not a civic magistrate. See Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 65.

118 Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 140.

119 Fröhlich 2004a, 266.

120 On the cosmopolitanism and broad horizons of the gymnasium crowd, see Schuler 2004a, 186. Consider also the shared iconography, the “international” or stock themes of statuary in the mid-Hellenistic gymnasium, for which see Hoff 2004, 391–93.

121 For the “règlementation minutieuse” of Philip V, see Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 145–46. The crucial text for Philip’s program of standardization is his partially published letter to Amphipolis (Hatzopoulos 1996, no. 16), on which see SEG XLIII 369; XLVI 717. Further on the Antigonid reform of ephebic life, see Intzesiloglou Reference Intzesiloglou and Pikoulas2006.

122 A. Chankowski 2009; cf. Prag Reference Prag2007, 99. Despite the efforts of activist kings, the gymnasia of Antigonid Macedonia were perhaps less standardized than one has supposed. In both Beroia and Amphipolis, royal law was adapted and harmonized with civic (Rousset Reference Rousset2017, 63–69).

123 The lack of any mention of the king led early commentators (SEG XXVII 261) to date the law after the fall of the dynasty. See now Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 125–26. Dreyer (2004, 234) adduces it as an example of a city asserting control over a gymnasium by one of several means at its disposal; also, Moretti Reference Moretti1982, 59.

124 For the meaning of pylôn, see Delorme Reference Delorme1960, 358; entryways more generally, Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 254. For the luminous royal portrait statue, see Robert 1960, 117–18; for the ancient meaning of exedra, as opposed to what epigraphers typically mean by it, see Hellmann Reference Hellmann1992, 126–30. The exedra is a full room or hall, at times with a porch attached, in other words, a much more substantial gift than a semi-circular statue base at the edge of the palaistra; cf. the exedra of SEG XXVI 139 line 45, which Ma 2008a places in a shrine of the Nymphs, not in an Athenian gymnasium as previously conjectured.

125 For kosmêsis, see first Robert 1937, 349 n. 1. However, that note belongs to the publication of an honorific decree for a gymnasiarch of Sebastopolis in Caria, from the second century CE. Only a portion of Robert’s parallels are to do with the gymnasium, and many of them are from Roman times. Yet these later benefactors have clearly inherited a Hellenistic model, one which may have been forged in the context of the gymnasium. See, for example, the decree of 196 BCE of the Xanthian neoi for Lyson, SEG XLVI 1721 lines 15–16: καὶ πολλὰ τῶν ἰδίων εἰς ανηλώσας ἐκόσμη| σεν (“and he decorated by spending much of his own money”); further, e.g., see the honors for Diodoros Pasparos from the gymnasium of Pergamon, MDAI(A) 32 (1907) 257,8.

126 Curty Reference Curty2015, 278.

127 Fröhlich 2009.

128 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 262a [E] line 47.

129 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, 304; ISE 149. On a related problem, note Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 215 [L], the gift of 75 talents for oil that Hieron II gave Rhodes. To many, this has seemed like too much money for oil alone. In fact, as a result, the text of Polyb. 5.88.5–8 has been amended with Diod. Sic. 26.8.1.

130 Gauthier 1995, 5; Dreyer 2004, 227.

131 For the public appointment of specialist instructors as a defining feature of the Hellenistic gymnasium, see Kah Reference Kah, Kah and Scholz2004, 63, with sources collected in Roesch Reference Roesch1982, 307–54. Aybek and Dreyer (2011, 212–13) suspect an Attalid ballistics trainer for ephebes at Metropolis.

132 SEG XXXII 496 (from Thespiai).

133 Delorme Reference Delorme1960, 304: “Point n’est besoin de montrer la nécessité de l’eau dans les gymnases.” The siting of gymnasia on hillsides also facilitated water conveyance (Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 252–53). On cold and hot baths (so-called Hellenistic Schwitzbaden) in this context, see Trümper 2014, 211–12.

134 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 298 [E]. However, an alternative interpretation exists: the benefactor might be one of the descendants of the original grant-holder, not Philip III. See Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, 371–72.

135 Pergamon: Radt 1999, 121; Hieron II: Ath. 5.207d.

136 Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 255. See also Delorme Reference Delorme1960, 446–47, on water needs as a determinative factor for the topography of the early gymnasium.

137 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, nos. 225–29 [E]; see also Savalli-Lestrade 2010, esp. 83. In her model, Hellenistic royalty came to monopolize the festival or sacred time of the cities. I am reluctant to go so far, but the royal dominance of the civic festival calendar certainly came at the expense of local observance. Moreover, as she demonstrates, once on the sacred books, it was actually very difficult to remove rites associated with even defunct dynasties.

138 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. *357 [E]. On these rooms and the increase in their functional differentiation over the course of the Hellenistic period, see Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 256–59; Trümper (Reference Trümper, Matthaei and Zimmermann2015, 169) sees such rooms as characteristic of late Hellenistic gymnasia. On libraries in gymnasia of this period, see Adak and Stauner Reference Adak and Stauner2018, 12 n. 37; Prag Reference Prag2007, 94.

139 Athenaios and Colophon: Gauthier 2006 = D10.

140 SEG L 1211 line 12.

141 See Wörrle 2007, 513. Indeed, Kennell (2015, 176) notes class tensions in the late second century (post-Attalid) gymnasium of Pergamon.

142 Gehrke 2004, 414–15.

143 On the emergence of an aristocracy in the Hellenistic city from the mid-second century, see Hamon 2007, 84.

144 SEG XXXIX 1244 = Claros I, 63–104 Column I lines 11–12.

145 Side B lines 27–29. Regarding apalaistroi, we find them making a dedication to a gymnasiarch in Demetrias, along with paides and οἱ ἐκ τοῦ γυμνασίου: A. S. Arvanitopoulos, Polemon 1 (1929), 126–28. It seems that a group of physically unfit youths might be eligible for distributions of oil that took place in the gymnasium, even if they found themselves excluded from the palaistra itself. See Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 81–84.

146 Contra Gehrke (2007, 418), who contends that all citizens had a de jure right to participate. For the ephebate, see full discussion of A. Chankowski Reference Chankowski, Fröhlich and Müller2010, 277–84. Note that the admission of noncitizens to the ephebate was rare before the influx of Romano-Italians. By contrast, Chankowski (p. 277) remarks on the regular participation of noncitizens in many other activities of the gymnasium.

147 Hatzopoulos 1996, vol. 1, 209 n. 1; see now text of Lazaridou Reference Lazaridou2015, lines 14–19. However, Hatzopoulos (2016, 155–56) suggests that fathers or tutors with property valued above 30 minas may have been required by royal writ to register their sons for the ephebate, making it a matter of choice for the poor. Rousset (Reference Rousset2017, 70–75) instead argues that lines 14–19 reflect conditions in the Augustan age, when the ephebate was obligatory for all citizens of Amphipolis.

148 Kennell Reference Kennell2006, x, citing Pélékidis 1962, 164–65.

149 Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 83: “Le passage par le gymnase ou par l’éphébie n’y constituait pas ou n’y constituait plus, pour autant que nous le sachions, l’étape obligée vers la citoyenneté ou vers quelque statut juridique privilégié.”

150 Thuc. 5.67.2; Diod. Sic. 12.75.7; Plut. Alc. 15.3.

151 Bremen Reference Bremen2013, 36–44.

152 Translation here and below of Side A line 42 from Jones 2004.

153 Contra Rowe Reference Rowe2002, 127–30.

154 Jones 2004, 483.

155 The rhetoric of the Metropolis decrees is in some ways rather banal. Formally, the Hellenistic honorific decree tends to reduce each individual biography to what Ma (2007, 218) calls a “cipher of civic virtue.” Ma’s essay, which characterizes the honorific decree as social constraint rather than sycophancy, has shaped my analysis here and in the following treatment of Eirenias of Miletus. The distinctiveness of the Metropolis case consists of repeated assimilation of the private (to idion) to the public (to koinon), particularly with regard to heroic cult.

156 Jones 2010, 35.

157 See also editions of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 283 [E 1]; I.Milet 1039.

158 The foundation of Eudemos provides the terminus ante quem for the other gymnasia (Milet I 3 145).

159 Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 254: the Eumenes-Gymnasion in Miletus and the gymnasium of Messene are exceptions to the rule that Hellenistic gymnasia do not share axial alignment with other major monuments and urban plans.

160 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 284 [E 2]. Schaaf (Reference Schaaf1992, 62) concludes that the propylon undoubtedly belongs to the gymnasium complex. See also Kleine Reference Kleine and Müller-Wiener1986 and esp. Emme Reference Emme2013, 269, 347–48, with Taf. 76, p. 464. Emme suggests that the “Westmarkt”/xystos could also be a second-century monument. See further Trümper Reference Trümper, Matthaei and Zimmermann2015, 196 n. 92.

161 The Milesians voted cultic honors for Eumenes in recompense for the foundation. On this exceptional lifetime deification, see further Allen Reference Allen1983, 114–19. These were announced to the king in a decree that Eirenias delivered. It is very likely that one of these honors was a temenos, the very precinct mentioned in RC 52 (line 60 of Welles’ text) and possibly the peristyle “Hofhaus am Athena-Tempel.” For the chronology, see the useful table of Herrmann 1965, 113–14.

162 Herrmann 1965, 111.

163 This is the unambiguous interpretation of Herrmann (1965, 78, 111), who translates synchôrêsis as “Erlaubnis” and “Zustimmung”; cf. I.Milet 1040: “Einverständnis,” pace Kleine Reference Kleine and Müller-Wiener1986, 131. For synchôrêsis, granted by the city to the gymnasium, cf. I.Pergamon 252 lines 39–40. For further evidence of the informal character of the first meeting of Eirenias and Eumenes, see the Milesian decree for Eumenes from the propylon of the gymnasium (I.Milet 307 lines 17–18). There, Eirenias’ presentation to the king regarding the gymnasium is described as τὰ τε ὑπὸ Εἰρ[η]|νίου ἐμφανισθέντα αὐτῶι (“the things explained to Eumenes by Eirenias”) – not as a decree of the Milesians.

164 Herrmann 1965, 111: “sich sichern.”

165 An interesting case is that of Rhodes, Hieron II, and Gelon II after the earthquake of 227/6 (Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 215 [L] = Polyb. 5.88.5–8; Diod. Sic. 26.8.1). Polybius records among other gifts, 10 talents πρὸς … τὴν ἐπαύξησιν τῶν πολιτῶν, a phrase commonly rendered simply as, “for the welfare of the citizenry,” whereas the oil is provided τοῖς ἐν τῷ γυμνασίῳ, “for those in the gymnasium.”

166 See Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 286 [E]. After the death of Eumenes II, the Milesians transferred some of the revenues of the gymnasium foundation to a different (new?) foundation for a ruler cult, which included a grain distribution to Milesian citizens. In his capacity as supervisor of the building of the gymnasium, curiously, Eirenias was responsible for the transfer of the money at the public bank.

167 E.g., Dreyer 2004, 234; Gauthier 1985, 67 n. 220; Hamon Reference Hamon, Fröhlich and Müller2009, 356–57.

168 Pleket Reference Pleket1973, 256.

169 Herrmann 1987, 175; I.Milet III, p. 23: “ein weiteres Mal in diplomatischer Mission am pergamenischen Hof”; Eirenias is designated as presbeutês in SEG XXXVI 1046 Block I line 9. The embassy in question delivered an honorific decree to Eumenes II voted in response to the gift of the gymnasium.

170 For this interpretation, see Bresson 2000, 131–49; cf. Hamon (2007, 357 n. 22), who sees tax immunity for goods exported from the city, not by the citizens.

171 Marcellesi (2004, 181 n. 93) best captures the subtlety of the situation beneath the rhetoric of the decree. Discarding an old idea about a thaw in Seleukid-Attalid relations, she envisions a skillful courtier playing the two dynasties against each other.

172 Compare the lengths of the bases: 2.65 m (Eirenias) and 1.64 m (Eumenes II). I.Milet III, p. 22: “ein wahrhaft ‘königliches’ Denkmal”; larger than the monument of Eumenes II: Kleine Reference Kleine and Müller-Wiener1986, 130. Note also that both Eirenias and Eumenes received gilded statues, as an honor that may have once been reserved for royals is transferred to the domain of civic benefactors. See Gauthier 1985, 46 n. 116. At Miletus, no one else seems to have received such a statue until early Imperial times. See Herrmann 1965, 87 n. 49. On the technique and proliferation of Hellenistic gilding, cf. Ma 2013b, 253–54. Ma attributes the late Hellenistic increase in gilded statues to the introduction of gold leaf.

173 The location of the temenos is controversial. One has suspected that it was near the future site of the gymnasium of Eumenes II, but the findspot of the remains of the king’s round monument was the so-called Hofhaus am Athena-tempel. See Kleine Reference Kleine and Müller-Wiener1986, 139.

174 For the findspot, see Kleine Reference Kleine and Müller-Wiener1986, 130. The blocks were discovered in a fountain house in a village southeast of the site.

175 Milet I 3 145 = Syll.3 577. The decision of the city is contained therein: to erect two stelai, one in the Delphinion, in an exedra dedicated by Eudemos himself, the other in the paidikê palaistra, in “which place seems appropriate (epitêdeion)” (lines 84–87).

176 Herrmann 1965, 88, where parallels are adduced.

177 Rhodes and Lewis Reference Rhodes and Lewis1997, 514–15, with Hellenistic parallels. On anxiety over the size and nature of public rewards for public benefactions, which appears already in fourth-century Athens, see Domingo Gygax Reference Domingo Gygax2016, 240–43.

178 Herrmann 1965, 88–89. Ma (2013b, 70–75) treats the mechanics and politics of the grants of public space (topos) for honorific portrait statues. When a city’s own assembly voted to erect a statue, the grant of a topos was a tautologous display of communal power. Normal practice was to appoint a magistrate or board to carry out the work (e.g., the archê appointed in I.Oropos 294). Any further review of the honors in the form of dokimasia represents, then, an important check on status-seekers. The Cyzikene priestess Kleidike is another one of the few on record facing such scrutiny. However, an assembly (demos) ratified her honors rather than a special court as in Eirenias’ Miletus (CIG 3657 = Michel, Recueil 537).

179 Gauthier 1985, 78: “dokimasia de la recompense.”

180 For the latest discussions of this inscription, see SEG LVI 193.

181 paides: Gauthier and Hatzopoulos Reference Gauthier and Hatzopoulos1993, 65–69; epheboi: Chankowski Reference Chankowski, Fröhlich and Müller2010; neoi: Dreyer 2004 and Bremen Reference Bremen2013; presbyteroi: Fröhlich 2013; apalaistroi: see above Footnote n. 145.

182 Kennell Reference Kennell2006, s.v. gymnasiou; Gauthier 2006, 485 n. 5; Adak and Stauner Reference Adak and Stauner2018, 11–12.

183 Van Bremen (Reference Bremen2013, 31–36) considers the definitional problem anew from the standpoint of the neoi.

184 Ziebarth Reference Ziebarth1896; Poland Reference Poland1909. See now also the regional corpora Kloppenborg and Ascough Reference Kloppenborg and Ascough2011; Kloppenborg et al. Reference Kloppenborg, Ascough and Harland2014, along with publications of the Copenhagen Associations Project, such as Gabrielsen and Thomsen 2015.

185 Fröhlich 2013, 67.

186 Since Granovetter Reference Granovetter1973, sociology has reconsidered the paradoxical strength of “weak ties” in social networks.

187 Never an age class nor even the porte-parole for one: Fröhlich 2013, 79–81.

188 From Attalid Teos, note also the oversight of the timouchoi, one of two leading boards of magistrates, in the administration of the property of the neoi (Adak and Stauner Reference Adak and Stauner2018, 20).

189 Diod. Sic. 18.46–47; for Van Bremen (Reference Bremen2013, 36–40), this episode is paradigmatic of her “disruptive neoi.” See further on the episode, Köse Reference Köse2017, 42–43.

190 For this genre of decrees, see Robert 1926, 507–9; Robert 1937, 149–52. According to Hamon (Reference Hamon, Fröhlich and Müller2009, 360–62), the prographê of the Council (boulê) was a normative feature of probouleutic deliberation in the Hellenistic polis. For neoi decrees as such, see Gauthier 1996, 1–34, esp. 9–11. An honorific decree from Roman Smyrna refers to a vote by three bodies: the gerousia, the neoi of the Mimnermeion, and the synodos of the paideutai (I.Smyrna I 215).

191 Gauthier 2006, 488.

192 Macridy Reference Macridy1905, 161–63; Gauthier 2006, 465, where the honors of the second decree are also qualified as “gymnasiaux.”

193 See the new edition of Gauthier 2005, 101–2.

194 Bremen Reference Bremen2013, 48.

195 See also the case of the neoi of Xanthos, SEG XLVI 1721, with text and analysis of Gauthier 1996. The neoi seek their city’s permission to have the gymnasiarch Lyson honored in the city’s main sanctuary, the Letôon.

196 The term does not appear in the index of Kennell Reference Kennell2006. He indicates (personal comm.) that he knows of no comparanda.

197 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, 252. However, contra, see IG XII 4 1 281: “concilium magistrorum.”

198 Paton and Hicks Reference Paton and Hicks1891, no. 43. Note also Maiuri Reference Maiuri1925, no. 434, on the Attalid connection to a shadowy politeuma on Kos. I am at a loss over this text. I cannot determine whether it relates to the gymnasium per se.

200 Fröhlich 2013, 66–79.

201 Eth. Nic. 1160a; cf. Eth. Eud. 1241b. The fourth century saw an explosion in the number of these associations. For Arnaoutoglou Reference Arnaoutoglou, Cartledge, Millett and von Reden1998, they contributed to the ideological coherence of the polis. Gabrielsen Reference Gabrielsen, Malkin, Constantakopoulou and Panagopoulou2009 expresses a less sanguine view.

202 Was the power of gymnasia also as great as it would ever be? Note that ca. 130, Ptolemy Euergetes II issued an edict liquidating the assets of all sorts of associations, certainly including gymnasia (Lenger 1964–88, no. 50).

203 Habicht 1995, 262: “Unregelmäßigkeit.”

204 The gymnasium of Delos received a great deal of royal patronage in the second century, but none of it Attalid. See Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, nos. 153, 189–91. As for the presence of royal figures in the gymnasium, while Roman emperors do appear in epigraphy as gymnasiarchs, Hellenistic kings do not – unless one follows Robert in taking one of the Attalids as the gymnasiarch of Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. *357 [E], from Aigai. The job requirements were too strict, though in late Hellenistic cities endowments produced “posthumous gymnasiarchs.” In Beroia, at least, the daily presence of the gymnasiarch was expected. Similarly, I know of no certain cases of princes enrolled as ephebes before the two Cappadocians in Athens in 79/8 (IG II2 1039 bi + ci + p). Thus, I am skeptical of the claim that a Nikomedes (the future III or IV; Bringmann et al. do not treat the issue) was an ephebe on Delos (Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 189 [E] = I.Delos 1580).

206 It is worth noting that the Ionic Temple R, which sits on a podium above the Upper Gymnasium, was produced in marble. According to Bielfeldt (2010, 185), the connotations of marble at Pergamon were exclusively royal, while Pirson (2012, 218) observes a conspicuous lack of marble in those spaces that both scholars deem civic, such as the Upper Agora, as compared with royal showpieces like the sanctuary of Athena or the Great Altar terrace. This may be further proof that Temple R, with its independent entrance, was not as well integrated with the ensemble of the gymnasium as the ephebic inscriptions on its wall might indicate. See Trümper Reference Trümper, Matthaei and Zimmermann2015, 176–77.

207 On these dedications, see Hoff 2004, 388–90.

209 Many architectural studies (Trümper 2014, 211 n. 35; Pirson 2012, 217; Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 254) point to Kobes Reference Kobes, Kah and Scholz2004, an epigraphical analysis of restrictions on access to the gymnasium, in order to justify the claim that access was restricted to citizens. Focusing on the law from Beroia, Kobes’ article in fact shows that exclusion was based not on citizenship, but rather on gender and social criteria. He also cites decrees from Miletus (Syll.3 577) and Teos (Syll.3 578) that imply the regular presence of foreign teachers.

210 Habicht 1995, 262.

211 Michel, Recueil 544 lines 19–20: τοῖς τε ἐφήβοις καὶ νέοις καὶ τοῖς|ἐπιδημοῦσιν ξένοις. On this text, see also Wilhelm, Neue Beiträge VI, 45–48.

212 SEG LIV 1101. On the apparent paradox of noncitizen participation in what scholarship has – from an etic perspective – categorized as civic life, see Ma 2008b, 376.

213 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 241 [E] lines 15–16; Claros I, 100.

214 For the “new symbolic frontiers” of aristocracy in the late Hellenistic polis, see Hamon 2007, 94.

215 Critilaos: IG XII 7 515. It should be noted, at Critilaos’ banquet, the youth of the city are required to be present; Elpinikos: IG XII 9 324 = Syll.3 714.

216 See SEG XLIX 1540 line 22.

217 Gauthier 1980, 212: “Le caractère religieux (exigent la participation physique) et nullement civique de la fête est ainsi fortement marqué.”

218 Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 17 [E]. Habicht 1982, 115–17, restores: [… σίτου]|τοῦ διαμε[τρουμένου τοῖς πολίταις εἰς τὴν σ]|τοὰν τὴν έν [τεῖ παλαίστρᾳ τοῦ γυμνασίου τοῦ]|βασιλέως Π[τολεμαίου κτλ.] (lines 1–4). My own autopsy of the stone in the Epigraphical Museum of Athens (EM 7473) revealed no further trace of the intended recipients of Ptolemy’s largesse, as the stone is broken on both sides. The restoration πολίταις seems suspect. See already Robert and Robert Reference Robert and Robert1948, 127–28. On the topographical relationships and pseudo-civic ideology of the Gymnasium of Ptolemy, see Cesare 2018, 219–29. Another possible exception is a distribution at a festival in Miletus with posthumous ruler cult for Eumenes II (Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 286 [E]). However, it is noteworthy that the Milesians had modified an earlier foundation of Eumenes II. All this points to the hazard of assuming citizen-only distributions in the gymnasium. Roussel (Reference Roussel1916, 188) refers to one such distribution at the Hermaia of the Athenian cleruchy of Salamis in 131/0. Yet in that text, the gymnasiarch in fact invites everyone (IG II 594 line 5).

219 Robert 1960, 122–23.

220 On the traditional chronology, Archippe of Kyme is also thought to have held sway in this period. For the low chronology, see Hamon 2005, 135–36; for the high, see Bremen 2008.

221 Fröhlich Reference Fröhlich2005, 245.

222 SEG XXXIX 1244 Block II lines 3641.

223 Étienne 2004, 104.

224 SEG XXXIX 1243 = Claros I, 1162.

225 The glykismos in particular, which Robert and Robert (Claros I, p. 50) see as invariably including noncitizens, may have originated in the gymnasium. See, e.g., I.Histriae 59 line 14.

226 See the ephebic lists of post-Attalid Pergamon: MDAI(A) 32 (1907) 416–20.

227 I.Sestos 1 = OGIS 339.

228 Gray 2020.

229 On late Hellenistic civic processions, see A. Chankowski 2005.

231 These explanations stem ultimately from Robert; the more Machiavellian ones go back to Rostovtzeff.

232 For the transitional “period charnière” in the evolution of the gymnasiarchy, see Curty 2015, 267–91. Appearance of presbyteroi: Fröhlich 2013, 91. Total absence of marble architecture from gymnasia before the second century: Hoff Reference Hoff, Kah and Scholz2009, 260. Note the lack of any marble (or any other stone remains) from the earliest, ostensibly third-century phases of the “Gymnasium of Ptolemy” in Athens. I cannot assume, as Cesare (Reference Cesare, Mania and Trümper2018, 216–17) does, that the “Gymnasium of Ptolemy” and the Diogeneion were major architectural erga of the last quarter of the third century, which transformed and “modernized” the built environment of Athens’ city center (yet failed to garner the attention of Herakleides Kritikos). Notably, Mavrojannis (2019, 1–10) argues that it was Ptolemy Lathyros who donated the “Gymnasium of Ptolemy” as a massive architectural complex in 116 BCE. In a similar vein, Prag Reference Prag2007 credits Roman administrators with raising the profile of the civic gymnasium in Sicily.

233 Maier 1959–61, no. 51 = Bringmann et al. Reference Bringmann, von Steuben, Ameling and Schmidt-Dounas1995, no. 231 [E]. For Migeotte (1992, 180), Attalos II is certainly possible; for Schalles (Reference Schalles1985, 105 n. 634), it must be Attalos II. While Bringmann et al. list Attalos I as the donor, neither historical nor epigraphical arguments favor either candidate decisively.

234 See Migeotte 1992, no. 60. An Attalid gift close in time to the Chian public subscription: Maier 1959–61, vol. 1, 194.

Figure 0

Graph 5.1 Royal gifts to gymnasia.

(Data from Bringmann et al., 1995)
Figure 1

Figure 5.1 Plan of the gymnasium of Pergamon in relation to adjacent monuments and current reconstruction of street grid.

(courtesy of Pergamon Excavation of the German Archaeological Institute; https://geoserver.dainst.org/maps/5548/view)
Figure 2

Figure 5.2 Gymnasium of Pergamon, looking east across the palaistra of the upper terrace.

(courtesy of Pergamon Excavation of the German Archaeological Institute; photo: Ulrich Mania)
Figure 3

Figure 5.3 Hellenistic Sikyon, view east/southeast from the terraces of the city’s gymnasium toward the adjacent agora.

(Sklifas Steven/Alamy Stock Photo)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Hastening to the Gymnasium
  • Noah Kaye, Michigan State University
  • Book: The Attalids of Pergamon and Anatolia
  • Online publication: 02 March 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009279567.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Hastening to the Gymnasium
  • Noah Kaye, Michigan State University
  • Book: The Attalids of Pergamon and Anatolia
  • Online publication: 02 March 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009279567.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Hastening to the Gymnasium
  • Noah Kaye, Michigan State University
  • Book: The Attalids of Pergamon and Anatolia
  • Online publication: 02 March 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009279567.006
Available formats
×