Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:50:25.107Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 4 - Contingency, Irony, Edification: Changing the Conversation about Truth

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Anthony J. Cascardi
Affiliation:
University of California, Berkeley
Get access

Summary

Pragmatism

From a pragmatist standpoint, questions like “What is truth?” “What is consciousness?” and “What is reality?” that the Cartesian model was designed to answer could better be understood by watching how we actually use words like “truth” and “consciousness.” This was the spirit in which Wittgenstein attempted to shift emphasis away from questions about essences and toward linguistic usage. His “therapeutic” approach to philosophy’s fundamental problems was to ask questions about the place of an utterance within the give-and-take of “language games.” This was the term that Wittgenstein adopted from Fritz Mauthner to describe the nature of language as a set of shared, rule-based practices. In his later work, Wittgenstein saw an utterance as more like a move in a game than an independently structured proposition. Whatever one says makes sense, if at all, in relation to other utterances, or as part of a web of contextual relations – but not as the manifestation of some deep-structure content. Similarly, Wittgenstein proposed that it was more fruitful to reframe questions about identity and essence in terms of “family resemblance.” (Wittgenstein may have derived that notion from Nietzsche, who used it when talking about language families.) Wittgenstein’s point was that things may be connected by overlapping similarities rather than by a single underlying feature.

Richard Rorty’s work carried these ideas forward, specifically by insisting that “truth” and “value” do not have any particular form or underlying essence aside from the ways in which such terms are used. Rorty, like Wittgenstein, wanted to return them from philosophy to the forms of our everyday practices. “Truth,” he said “is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically interesting theory about.” So too with value: “[Pragmatists] see certain acts as good to perform, under the circumstances, but doubt that there is anything general and useful to say about what makes them all good” (xiii). It is worth noting that Voltaire’s Philosophical Dictionary has no entry for “truth,” although it does have one for “tolerance.” “We are all steeped in weakness and error,” writes Voltaire; “let us forgive one another’s follies, it is the first law of nature.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Dialogue and Dialectic, trans. Christopher Smith, P. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method, revised trans. Weinsheimer, Joel and Marshall, Donald G. (New York: Continuum, 1995).Google Scholar
Long, Anthony A., Epictetus: A Stoic and Socratic Guide to Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schleiermacher, Friedrich, Hermeneutics and Criticism, trans. and ed. Bowie, Andrew (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shusterman, Richard, Practicing Philosophy: Pragmatism and the Philosophical Life (New York: Routledge, 1997).Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, The Possibility of Practical Reason (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Library, 2000).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×