Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2014
Pragmatism
From a pragmatist standpoint, questions like “What is truth?” “What is consciousness?” and “What is reality?” that the Cartesian model was designed to answer could better be understood by watching how we actually use words like “truth” and “consciousness.” This was the spirit in which Wittgenstein attempted to shift emphasis away from questions about essences and toward linguistic usage. His “therapeutic” approach to philosophy’s fundamental problems was to ask questions about the place of an utterance within the give-and-take of “language games.” This was the term that Wittgenstein adopted from Fritz Mauthner to describe the nature of language as a set of shared, rule-based practices. In his later work, Wittgenstein saw an utterance as more like a move in a game than an independently structured proposition. Whatever one says makes sense, if at all, in relation to other utterances, or as part of a web of contextual relations – but not as the manifestation of some deep-structure content. Similarly, Wittgenstein proposed that it was more fruitful to reframe questions about identity and essence in terms of “family resemblance.” (Wittgenstein may have derived that notion from Nietzsche, who used it when talking about language families.) Wittgenstein’s point was that things may be connected by overlapping similarities rather than by a single underlying feature.
Richard Rorty’s work carried these ideas forward, specifically by insisting that “truth” and “value” do not have any particular form or underlying essence aside from the ways in which such terms are used. Rorty, like Wittgenstein, wanted to return them from philosophy to the forms of our everyday practices. “Truth,” he said “is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically interesting theory about.” So too with value: “[Pragmatists] see certain acts as good to perform, under the circumstances, but doubt that there is anything general and useful to say about what makes them all good” (xiii). It is worth noting that Voltaire’s Philosophical Dictionary has no entry for “truth,” although it does have one for “tolerance.” “We are all steeped in weakness and error,” writes Voltaire; “let us forgive one another’s follies, it is the first law of nature.”
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.