Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2014
“Truth consisteth in the right ordering of names in our affirmations.”
Hobbes, LeviathanThe area of ordinary language philosophy discussed in Chapter 9 is one of a number of instances where philosophy in the twentieth century made a turn toward language. This “linguistic turn” implied a turn away from a set of questions that had been dominant in philosophy for the previous few centuries. Beginning with Descartes, those questions had come to center around the relationship between the mind and the world. Questions of truth and value were organized around epistemology, which saw itself as “first philosophy.” The linguistic turn displaced those concerns with an interest in the relationship between language and the world. This did not come about for any accidental reason, but rather because it was hoped that the philosophy of language could answer questions that epistemology could not resolve. The linguistic turn did not leave everything else in place. Language involves questions of reference and meaning, and a satisfactory understanding of such things can’t be produced simply by replacing the notion of mental representations with the notion of linguistic representations.
I will have more to say about this shifting terrain over the course of what follows, but first we should indicate the role that literature had to play in the evolution of these views. First, literature is a form of discourse where meaning is crucial and yet is hardly dependent on a belief that the function of language is to represent the world. It is not at all clear that all literary language “represents” or “refers” at all. Second, literature is a domain where various kinds of “non-literal” meanings (including metaphor and other examples of figurative speech) are fundamental. Third, literature is a domain in which the “intentions” of speakers cannot be assessed in the ways in which we might assess the intentions of speakers in other contexts. The intentions of the narrator in a novel by Tolstoy, of a character in a play by Schiller, or of the speaking “I” in a poem by John Ashbery are not fathomable according to a single scheme of what “intention” may mean, and may not align with our understanding of intentions in ordinary speech at all.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.