Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of Contributors
- Preface
- Part I Academic Cheating
- Part II Academic Excuses and Fairness
- Part III Authorship and Credit
- Part IV Confidentiality’s Limits
- Part V Data Analysis, Reporting, and Sharing
- 27 Clawing Back a Promising Paper
- 28 When the Data and Theory Don’t Match
- 29 Desperate Data Analysis by a Desperate Job Candidate
- 30 Own Your Errors
- 31 Caution in Data Sharing
- 32 The Conflict Entailed in Using a Post Hoc Theory to Organize a Research Report
- 33 Commentary to Part V
- Part VI Designing Research
- Part VII Fabricating Data
- Part VIII Human Subjects
- Part IX Personnel Decisions
- Part X Reviewing and Editing
- Part XI Science for Hire and Conflict of Interest
- Epilogue Why Is Ethical Behavior Challenging?
- Index
- References
32 - The Conflict Entailed in Using a Post Hoc Theory to Organize a Research Report
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 February 2015
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of Contributors
- Preface
- Part I Academic Cheating
- Part II Academic Excuses and Fairness
- Part III Authorship and Credit
- Part IV Confidentiality’s Limits
- Part V Data Analysis, Reporting, and Sharing
- 27 Clawing Back a Promising Paper
- 28 When the Data and Theory Don’t Match
- 29 Desperate Data Analysis by a Desperate Job Candidate
- 30 Own Your Errors
- 31 Caution in Data Sharing
- 32 The Conflict Entailed in Using a Post Hoc Theory to Organize a Research Report
- 33 Commentary to Part V
- Part VI Designing Research
- Part VII Fabricating Data
- Part VIII Human Subjects
- Part IX Personnel Decisions
- Part X Reviewing and Editing
- Part XI Science for Hire and Conflict of Interest
- Epilogue Why Is Ethical Behavior Challenging?
- Index
- References
Summary
Kerr (1998) discusses in a very thorough and thoughtful manner the ethical dilemma that I faced many years earlier in seeking to bring a research report (Wallsten, 1976) to publication. Kerr called it HARKing, hypothesizing after the results are known. HARKing can take many forms, some of which are more egregious than others, but the essence of it is that a hypothesis, explanation, or theory developed to explain a data set or a pattern of results is introduced as motivating the experiment in the first place. Kerr (1998) documents the fact that in recent years at least some authors and research mentors have suggested, if not actually encouraged, putting ex post facto hypotheses at the front of the paper for a host of possible reasons, including that the paper becomes more readable.
We are (or at least, were) trained from graduate days on – actually for many of us, from undergraduate days on – not to present empirical research as support for a theory that grew from that very research. In broad outline form, the scientific method entails deducing predictions from theory and then testing them in an experiment. The theory accrues support if its predictions are sustained. Other possible outcomes are that the data provide partial support for the theory and the basis for revision or that they disconfirm it altogether, ideally simultaneously suggesting a new theory or perspective. The revisions or new theory are tested in a new experiment and the cycle continues. This is a very gross characterization of the ....-deduction-inference-deduction-inference-.... chain that links theory development and testing, but it captures the very important point that theories gain support on the basis of the outcomes of experiments designed to test them. It is misleading and a gross violation of scientific principles to develop an explanation for a set of data and then to present that data as supporting the explanation.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Ethical Challenges in the Behavioral and Brain SciencesCase Studies and Commentaries, pp. 94 - 97Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2015