Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T10:34:50.753Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

33 - Schaffner on Levels and Selves

from Section 11

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 April 2020

Kenneth S. Kendler
Affiliation:
Virginia Commonwealth University
Josef Parnas
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen
Peter Zachar
Affiliation:
Auburn University, Montgomery
Get access

Summary

Two concepts figure prominently in Schaffner’s discussion of LeDoux’s account of fear and anxiety: level and self. With respect to level, I differentiate two conceptions of levels invoked in his account: levels of hypotheses (high-level and intermediate-level instantiations) and mechanistic levels involving components within mechanisms. Both are important for Schaffner’s purposes, but they operate differently and should be distinguished. Schaffner’s account of self focuses on personality, but I suggest that more relevant is how one represents oneself, including one’s personality. I develop Neisser’s account of five types of knowledge one might have about oneself and argue that Neisser’s conceptual self is of the most use in understanding LeDoux’s account of fear. I conclude by suggesting how the representation of oneself may be developed differently at different levels of theorizing about oneself.

Type
Chapter
Information
Levels of Analysis in Psychopathology
Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives
, pp. 410 - 418
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baluška, F., & Levin, M. (2016) ‘On having no head: Cognition throughout biological systems.’ Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 902. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00902Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. (2008) Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Craver, C. F. (2007) Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970) ‘Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes.’ In Lakatos, I. & Musgrave, A. (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
LeDoux, J. E., & Brown, R. (2017) ‘A higher-order theory of emotional consciousness.’ Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 114, E2016E2025.Google Scholar
LeDoux, J. E., & Pine, D. S. (2016) ‘Using neuroscience to help understand fear and anxiety: A two-system framework.’ American Journal of Psychiatry, 173, 10831093.Google Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000) ‘Thinking about mechanisms.’ Philosophy of Science, 67, 125.Google Scholar
Neisser, U. (1988) ‘Five kinds of self-knowledge.’ Philosophical Psychology, 1, 3539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schacter, D. L. (1996) Searching for memory: The brain, the mind, and the past. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R., & Buckner, R. L. (2007) ‘Remembering the past to imagine the future: The prospective brain.’ Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 8, 657661.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1956) ‘Empiricism and the philosophy of mind.’ In Feigl, H. & Scriven, M. (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. I. The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 253329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, J. A. (2007) ‘Bacteria are small but not stupid: Cognition, natural genetic engineering and socio-bacteriology.’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 38, 807819.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. (1983) Elements of episodic memory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×