Alfano, M. (
2012).
Expanding the situationist challenge to responsibilist virtue epistemology.
Philosophical Quarterly,
62(247),
223–49.
Google Scholar Alfano, M. (
2013).
Character as Moral Fiction.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Alfano, M. (In press a). Extending the situationist challenge to reliabilism about inference. In
A. Fairweather (ed.)
Virtue Scientia: Bridges between Philosophy of Science and Virtue Epistemology.
Dordrecht, the Netherlands:
Springer.
Google Scholar Alfano, M. (In press b). What are the bearers of virtues? In
H. Sarkissian and
J. Wright (eds.)
Advances in Moral Psychology.
New York:
Continuum.
Google Scholar Alfano, M. and
Fairweather, A. (In press). Situationism and virtue theory.
Oxford Bibliographies: Philosophy.
Google Scholar Allport, G. and
Odbert, H. (
1936).
Trait Names: A Psycho-Lexical Study. Psychological Monographs 47.
Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Google Scholar Anscombe, G. E. M. (
1958).
Modern moral philosophy.
Philosophy,
33(124),
1–19.
Google Scholar Aristotle. (
1998).
The Nicomachean Ethics, trans.
D. Ross.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Aronson, J.,
Lustina, M.,
Good, C.,
Keough, K.,
Steele, C., and
Brown, J. (
1999).
When white men can’t do math: necessary and sufficient factors in stereotype threat.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
35,
29–46.
Google Scholar Asch, S. E. (
1952).
Social Psychology.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Google Scholar Ashton, M. and
Lee, K. (
2001).
A theoretical basis for the major dimensions of personality.
European Journal of Personality,
15,
327–53.
Google Scholar Ashton, M. and
Lee, K. (
2005).
Honesty-humility, the Big Five, and the Five-Factor model.
Journal of Personality,
73,
1321–53.
Google Scholar Austin, J. L. (
1962).
How to Do Things with Words.
London:
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Axtell, G. (
1997).
Recent work in virtue epistemology.
American Philosophical Quarterly,
34,
410–30.
Google Scholar Axtell, G. (
2000).
Knowledge, Belief, and Character.
Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield.
Google Scholar Axtell, G. (
2010).
Agency ascriptions in ethics and epistemology: or, navigating intersections, narrow and broad.
Metaphilosophy,
41,
73–94.
Google Scholar Baehr, J. (
2011).
The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology.
Oxford University Press.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Baril, A. (
2010).
A eudaimonist approach to the problem of significance.
Acta Analytica,
25(2),
215–41.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Barker, S. (
2000).
Is value content a component of conventional implicature?Analysis,
60(3),
268–79.
Google Scholar Battaly, H. (
2008).
Virtue epistemology.
Philosophy Compass,
3(4),
639–63.
Google Scholar Battaly, H. (
2010). Epistemic self-indulgence. In
H. Battaly (ed.)
Virtue and Vice, pp.
215–35.
Malden, MA:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Google Scholar Bedau, M. (
1991).
Can biological teleology be naturalized?Journal of Philosophy,
88,
647–55.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Benbow, C. and
Stanley, J. (
1980).
Sex differences in mathematical ability: fact or artifact?Science,
210,
1262–64.
Google Scholar Benbow, C. and
Stanley, J. (
1983).
Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability: more facts.
Science,
222,
1029–31.
Google Scholar Berker, S. (
2013).
Epistemic teleology and the separateness of propositions.
Philosophical Review,
122,
337–93.
Google Scholar Berker, S. (Unpublished manuscript). The rejection of epistemic consequentialism.
Google Scholar Bermudez, J. L. (
2003).
Thinking without Words.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Bishop, M. and
Trout, J. D. (
2005).
Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Blackburn, S. (
1998).
Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Blackburn, S. (
2011).
Practical Tortoise Raising and Other Philosophical Essays.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Blackwell, L.,
Trzesniewski, K., and
Dweck, C. (
2007).
Implicit theories of intelligence predict achievement across an adolescent transition: a longitudinal study and an intervention.
Child Development,
78(1),
246–63.
Google Scholar Blascovich, J.,
Spencer, S.,
Quinn, D., and
Steele, C. (
2001).
African-Americans and high blood pressure: the role of stereotype threat.
Psychological Science,
12,
225–29.
CrossRef | Google Scholar | PubMed Block, J. (
1995).
A contrarian view of the Five-Factor approach to personality description.
Psychological Bulletin,
117,
187–215.
Google Scholar Block, N. (
1996).
How heritability misleads about race.
Boston Review,
20(6),
30–35.
Google Scholar Bloomfield, P. (
2000).
Virtue epistemology and the epistemology of virtue.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
60(1),
23–43.
Google Scholar Boag, S. (
2011).
Explanation in personality psychology: “verbal magic” and the Five-Factor model.
Philosophical Psychology,
24,
223–43.
Google Scholar Bogg, T. and
Roberts, B. (
2004).
Conscientiousness and health-related behaviors: a meta-analysis of the leading behavioral contributors to mortality.
Psychological Bulletin,
130,
887–919.
CrossRef | Google Scholar | PubMed Boghossian, P. (
1997). Analyticity. In
B. Hale and
C. Wright (eds.)
Companion to the Philosophy of Language, pp.
331–68.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Boghossian, P. (
2003a).
Epistemic analyticity: a defense.
Grazer Philosophische Studien,
66,
15–35.
Google Scholar Boghossian, P. (
2003b).
The normativity of content.
Philosophical Issues,
13,
31–45.
Google Scholar Boghossian, P. (
2005). Is meaning normative? In
C. Nimtz and
A. Beckermann (eds.)
Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy, pp.
205–18.
Paderborn:
Mentis.
Google Scholar Boghossian, P. (
2006).
Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Boghossian, P. (In press).
What is inference?Philosophical Studies.
Google Scholar BonJour, L. (
1998).
In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar BonJour, L. (
2005). In defense of the a priori. In
M. Steup and
E. Sosa (eds.)
Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, pp.
98–105.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Boyd, R. (
1988). How to be a moral realist. In
G. Sayre-McCord (ed.)
Essays on Moral Realism, pp.
181–228.
Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Google Scholar Brink, D. O. (
1989).
Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Burge, T. (
2003).
Perceptual entitlement.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
67(3),
503–48.
Google Scholar Burge, T. (
2010).
Origins of Objectivity.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Buss, D. (
1996). Social adaptation and five major factors of personality. In
J. Wiggins (ed.)
The Five-Factor Model of Personality: Theoretical Perspectives, pp.
180–207.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Cadinu, M.,
Maass, A.,
Frigerio, S.,
Impagliazzo, L., and
Latinotti, S. (
2003).
Stereotype threat: the effect of expectancy on performance.
European Journal of Social Psychology,
33,
267–85.
Google Scholar Caprara, G. and
Cervone, D. (
2000).
Personality: Determinants, Dynamics, and Potentials.
Cambridge University Press.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Carroll, L. (
1895).
What the tortoise said to Achilles.
Mind,
14,
278–80.
Google Scholar Caspi, A.,
Roberts, B., and
Shiner, R. (
2005).
Personality development: stability and change.
Annual Review of Psychology,
56,
453–84.
Google Scholar Cervone, D. (
1999). Bottom-up explanation in personality psychology: the case of cross-situational coherence. In
D. Cervone and
Y. Shoda (eds.)
The Coherence of Personality: Social-Cognitive Bases of Consistency, Variability, and Organization, pp.
303–41.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Cervone, D.,
Shoda, Y., and
Downey, G. (
2007). Construing persons in context: on building a science of the individual. In
Y. Shoda,
D. Cervone, and
G. Downey (eds.)
Persons in Context: Building a Science of the Individual, pp.
3–15.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Chrisman, M. (
2007).
From epistemic contextualism to epistemic expressivism.
Philosophical Studies,
135,
225–54.
Google Scholar Chrisman, M. (
2011). From epistemic expressivism to epistemic inferentialism. In
A. Haddock,
A. Millar, and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
Social Epistemology, pp.
112–28.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Chrisman, M. (In press).
Epistemic expressivism.
Philosophy Compass.
Google Scholar Clark, A. and
Chalmers, D. (
1998).
The extended mind.
Analysis,
58(1),
7–19.
Google Scholar Cohen, G.,
Garcia, J.,
Apfel, N., and
Master, A. (
2006).
Reducing the racial achievement gap: a social-psychological intervention.
Science,
313,
1307–10.
Google Scholar Cohen, S. (
2002).
Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
65,
309–29.
Google Scholar Conee, E. and
Feldman, R. (
1998).
The generality problem for reliabilism.
Philosophical Studies,
89,
1–29.
Google Scholar Coplan, A. (
2010). Feeling without thinking. In
H. Battaly (ed.)
Virtue and Vice, pp.
133–51.
Malden, MA:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Google Scholar Copp, D. (
1995).
Morality, Normativity, and Society.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Copp, D. (
2001).
Realist-expressivism: a neglected option for moral realism.
Social Philosophy and Policy,
1(8),
21–43.
Google Scholar Copp, D. (
2009).
Toward a pluralist and teleological theory of normativity.
Philosophical Issues,
19,
21–37.
Google Scholar Cosmides, L. and
Tooby, J. (
1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In
J. Barkow,
L. Cosmides, and
J. Tooby (eds.)
The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, pp.
163–228.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Costa, P. and
McCrae, R. (
1992).
Revised NEO Personality Inventory (NEO-PI-R) and NEO Five-Factor Inventory (NEO-FFI) Professional Manual.
Odessa, TX:
Psychological Assessment Resources.
Google Scholar Costa, P. and
McCrae, R. (
1994). “Set like plaster”? Evidence for the stability of adult personality. In
T. Heatherton and
J. Weinberger (eds.)
Can Personality Change?, pp.
21–40.
Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Google Scholar Costa, P. and
McCrae, R. (
1995).
Domains and facets: hierarchical personality assessment using the revised NEO personality inventory.
Journal of Personality Assessment,
64,
21–50.
Google Scholar Craig, E. (
1990).
Knowledge and the State of Nature.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Croizet, J. and
Claire, T. (
1998).
Extending the concept of stereotype threat to social class: the intellectual underperformance of students from low socioeconomic backgrounds.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
24,
588–94.
Google Scholar Cruz, J. and
Pollock, J. (
2004). The chimerical appeal of epistemic externalism. In
R. Schantz (ed.)
The Externalist Challenge, pp.
125–42.
Berlin:
De Gruyter.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Cuneo, T. (
2007).
The Normative Web.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Danaher, K. and
Crandall, C. (
2008).
Stereotype threat in applied settings re-examined.
Journal of Applied Social Psychology,
38,
1639–55.
Google Scholar Darley, J. M. and
Batson, C. D. (
1973).
From Jerusalem to Jericho.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
27,
100–8.
Google Scholar Dennett, D. (
1984).
Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Dennett, D. (
1989).
The Intentional Stance.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Dewey, J. (
1910).
How We Think.
New York:
D. C. Heath & Co.
Google Scholar DeYoung, C.,
Quilty, L., and
Peterson, J. (
2007).
Between facets and domains: 10 aspects of the Big Five.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
93,
880–96.
Google Scholar Digman, J. (
1990).
Personality structure: emergence of the Five-Factor model.
Annual Review of Psychology,
41,
417–40.
Google Scholar Dogramaci, S. (
2012).
Reverse engineering epistemic evaluations.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84(3), pp. 513–530.
Google Scholar Doris, J. M. (
1998).
Persons, situations, and virtue ethics.
Noûs,
32,
504–30.
Google Scholar Doris, J. M. (
2002).
Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Doris, J. and
Olin, L. (In press).
Vicious minds: virtue, cognition, and skepticism.
Philosophical Studies.
Google Scholar Dretske, F. I. (
1981).
Knowledge and the Flow of Information.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Dretske, F. I. (
2000). Norms, history, and the constitution of the mental. In
Perception, Knowledge, and Belief: Selected Essays, pp.
242–58.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Drier, J. (
2001). Humean doubts about categorical imperatives. In
E. Millgram (ed.)
Varieties of Practical Reasoning, pp.
27–47.
Boston:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Duncker, K. (
1945).
On Problem Solving, trans.
L. S. Lees. Psychological Monographs 58.
Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Google Scholar Dweck, C. (
1999).
Self-Theories: Their Role in Motivation, Personality, and Development.
Philadelphia:Taylor and Francis/Psychology Press.
Google Scholar Dweck, C.,
Chiu, C., and
Hong, Y. (
1995).
Implicit theories and their role in judgments and reactions: a world from two perspectives.
Psychological Inquiry,
6(4),
267–85.
Google Scholar Epstein, S. (
1994).
Trait theory as personality theory: can a part be as great as the whole?Psychological Inquiry,
5(2),
120–22.
Google Scholar Evans, I. and
Smith, N. D. (
2012).
Knowledge.
Cambridge:
Polity.
Google Scholar Fairweather, A. (
2001). Epistemic motivation. In
A. Fairweather and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, pp.
63–81.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Fairweather, A. and
Montemayor, C. (In press).
The meeting of the twain: Alfano on situationism and virtue epistemology.
Philosophical Quarterly.
Google Scholar Feldman, R. (
2001). Voluntary belief and epistemic evaluation. In
M. Steup (ed.)
Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, pp.
77–92.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Feldman, R. and
Conee, E. (
2001). Internalism defended. In
H. Kornblith (ed.)
Epistemology: Internalism and Externalism, pp.
231–60.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Feldman, R. and
Cullison, A. (
2012). Evidentialism. In
A. Cullison (ed.)
The Continuum Companion to Epistemology, pp.
92–105.
New York:
Continuum.
Google Scholar Field, H. (
2006). Recent debates about the a priori. In
T. Gendler and
J. Hawthorne (eds.)
Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol.
i, pp.
69–88.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Field, H. (
2009).
Epistemology without metaphysics.
Philosophical Studies,
143,
249–90.
Google Scholar Finlay, S. (
2004).
The conversational practicality of value judgement.
Journal of Ethics,
8(3),
205–23.
Google Scholar Finlay, S. (
2005).
Value and implicature.
Philosophers’ Imprint,
5(4),
1–20.
Google Scholar Firth, R. (
1981).
Epistemic merit, intrinsic and instrumental.
Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association,
55,
5–23.
Google Scholar Flanagan, O. J. (
1991).
Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism.
Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar Flanagan, O. J. (
2006). Varieties of naturalism. In
P. Clayton and
Z. Simpson (eds.)
The Oxford Companion to Religion and Science, pp.
430–52.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Flanagan, O. J. (
2009). Moral science? Still metaphysical after all these years. In
D. Narvaez and
D. Lapsley (eds.)
Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology, pp.
54–65.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Fodor, J. A. (
1983).
The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Fodor, J. A. (
2000).
The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Foley, R. (
1987).
The Theory of Epistemic Rationality.
Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Foley, R. (
1993).
Working without a Net.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Foot, P. (
1972).
Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives.
Philosophical Review,
81(3),
305–16.
Google Scholar Foot, P. (
2001).
Natural Goodness.
Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Foot, P. (
2010).
Exemplarist virtue theory.
Metaphilosophy,
41(1/2),
41–57.
Google Scholar Forgas, J.-P. and
East, R. (
2008).
On being happy and gullible: mood effects on skepticism and the detection of deception.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
4(4),
1362–67.
Google Scholar Fricker, M. (
2007).
Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Frieman, J. (
2002).
Learning and Adaptive Behavior.
South Melbourne, Australia:
Wadsworth.
Google Scholar Fumerton, R. (
2001). Epistemic justification and normativity. In
M. Steup (ed.)
Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, pp.
49–60.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Fumerton, R. (
2008). Externalism and skepticism. In
E. Sosa,
J. Kim,
J. Fantl, and
M. McGrath (eds.)
Epistemology: An Anthology, pp.
394–406.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Gibbard, A. (
1990).
Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Gibbard, A. (
2003).
Thinking How to Live.
Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar Gigerenzer, G. (
2007).
Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the Unconscious.
New York:
Viking.
Google Scholar Gigerenzer, G. (
2008).
Rationality for Mortals: How People Cope with Uncertainty.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Glover, S. and
Dixon, P. (
2002).
Semantics affect the planning but not control of grasping.
Experimental Brain Research,
146(3),
383–87.
Google Scholar Goldberg, L. (
1981). Language and individual differences: the search for universals in personality lexicons. In
L. Wheeler (ed.)
Review of Personality and Social Psychology, vol.
ii, pp.
141–65.
Beverly Hills:
Sage.
Google Scholar Goldberg, L. (
1992).
The development of markers for the Big-Five factor structure.
Psychological Assessment,
4,
26–42.
Google Scholar Goldberg, L. (
1993).
The structure of phenotypic personality traits.
American Psychologist,
48,
26–34.
Google Scholar Goldberg, L. and
Saucier, G. (
1995).
So what do you propose we use instead? A reply to Block.
Psychological Bulletin,
117,
221–25.
Google Scholar Goldberg, S. (
2012). Reliabilism. In
A. Cullison (ed.)
The Continuum Companion to Epistemology, pp.
106–23.
New York:
Continuum.
Google Scholar Goldman, A. I. (
1988).
Strong and weak justification.
Philosophical Perspectives,
13,
51–69.
Google Scholar Goldman, A. I. (
1992). Epistemic folkways and scientific epistemology. In
A. I. Goldman (ed.)
Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences, pp.
155–75.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Goldman, A. I. (
1994).
Naturalistic epistemology and reliabilism.
Midwest Studies in philosophy,
19(1),
301–20.
Google Scholar Goldman, A. I. (
1999).
Knowledge in a Social World.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Goldman, A. I. (
2001). The internalist conception of justification. In
H. Kornblith (ed.)
Epistemology: Internalism and Externalism, pp.
36–67.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Goldstone, R. L. (
2003). Learning to perceive while perceiving to learn. In
M. Kimchi,
M. Behrmann, and
C. Olson (eds.)
Perceptual Organization in Vision: Behavioral and Neural Perspectives, pp.
233–78.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Google Scholar Good, C.,
Aronson, J., and
Harder, J. A. (
2008).
Problems in the pipeline: stereotype threat and women’s achievement in high-level math courses.
Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology,
29,
17–28.
Google Scholar Good, C.,
Dweck, C., and
Rattan, A. (Unpublished data). An incremental theory decreases vulnerability to stereotypes about math ability in college females. Columbia University,
2005.
Google Scholar Goodale, M. A. (
2010).
Transforming vision into action.
Vision Research,
10(1016),
7–27.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (
2010). Testimonial entitlement and the function of comprehension. In
A. Haddock,
A. Millar, and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
Social Epistemology, pp.
148–75.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (
2011a). Psychological capacity and positive epistemic status. In
J. G. Hernandez (ed.)
The New Intuitionism, pp.
128–51.
London:
Continuum.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (
2011b).
Does justification aim at truth?Canadian Journal of Philosophy,
41,
51–72.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (
2011c).
Perceptual entitlement and basic beliefs.
Philosophical Studies,
153,
467–75.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (
2012b). Epistemic value and proper function. Paper presented to the 2012 meeting of the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association, Seattle, WA.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (In press a). Perceptual entitlement and natural norms. In
P. Graham and
N. J. Pedersen (eds.)
Epistemic Entitlement: Warrant without Reason.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (In press b). The function of perception. In
A. Fairweather (ed.)
Virtue Scientia: Bridges between Philosophy of Science and Virtue Epistemology.
Dordrecht, the Netherlands:
Springer.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (In press c). Epistemic evaluation and social norms. In
J. Greco and
D. Henderson (eds.)
Epistemic Evaluations.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (Unpublished manuscript a). Epistemic normativity as performance normativity.
Google Scholar Graham, P. J. (Unpublished manuscript b). Two conceptions of warrant.
Google Scholar Grant, H. and
Dweck, C. (
2003).
Clarifying achievement goals and their impact.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
85,
541–53.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
1993).
Virtues and vices of virtue epistemology.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy,
23(3),
413–32.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
1999).
Agent reliabilism.
Noûs,
33(s13),
273–96.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2000).
Putting Skeptics in Their Place: The Nature of Skeptical Arguments and Their Role in Philosophical Inquiry.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2003). Knowledge as credit for true belief. In
M. DePaul and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, pp.
111–34.
Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2007).
The nature of ability and the purpose of knowledge.
Philosophical Issues,
17,
57–69.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2008).
What’s wrong with contextualism?Philosophical Quarterly,
58,
416–36.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2009).
Knowledge and success from ability.
Philosophical Studies,
142,
17–26.
Google Scholar Greco, J. (
2010).
Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Greco, J. and
Groff, R. eds. (
2013).
Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism.
Abingdon:
Routledge.
Google Scholar Grimm, S. R. (
2006).
Is understanding a species of knowledge?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
57(3),
515–35.
Google Scholar Grimm, S. R. (
2008).
Epistemic goals and epistemic values.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
77(3),
725–44.
Google Scholar Grimm, S. R. (
2009). Epistemic normativity. In
A. Haddock,
A. Millar, and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
Epistemic Value, pp.
243–64.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Grimm, S. R. and
Ahlstrom, K. (
2013).
Getting it right.
Philosophical Studies,
166(2),
329–47.
Google Scholar Harman, G. (
1999).
Moral philosophy meets social psychology: virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
99,
315–31.
Google Scholar Harman, G. (
2000).
The nonexistence of character traits.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
100,
223–26.
Google Scholar Harrison, L.,
Stevens, C.,
Monty, A., and
Coakley, C. (
2006).
The consequences of stereotype threat on the academic performance of white and non-white lower income college students.
Social Psychology of Education,
9,
341–57.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Hatfield, E.,
Cacioppo, J., and
Rapson, R. (
1994).
Emotional Contagion.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Hazlett, A. (
2012).
Non-moral evil.
Midwest Studies in Philosophy,
36,
18–34.
Google Scholar Hazlett, A. (
2013).
A Luxury of the Understanding: On the Value of True Belief.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Hazlett, A. (Unpublished manuscript). Limning structure as an epistemic goal.
Google Scholar Hempel, Carl (
1959). The logic of functional analysis. In L. Gross (ed.)
Symposium on Sociological Theory, pp.
271–307.
New York:
Harper & Row.
Google Scholar Henderson, D. and
Horgan, T. (
2001).
Practicing safe epistemology.
Philosophical Studies,
102,
227–58.
Google Scholar Henderson, D. and
Horgan, T. (
2011).
The Epistemological Spectrum: At the Interface of Cognitive Science and Conceptual Analysis.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Henrich, J.,
Heine, S. J., and
Norenzayan, A. (
2010).
The weirdest people in the world?Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
33(2–3),
61–83. doi:
10.1017/s0140525x0999152x.
Google Scholar Herrnstein, R. and
Murray, C. (
1996).
The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure in American Life.
New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Google Scholar Hieronymi, P. (
2005).
The wrong kind of reason.
Journal of Philosophy,
102(9),
437–57.
Google Scholar Higgins, E. Tory. (
1996). Knowledge activation: accessibility, applicability, and salience. In
E. T. Higgins and
A. W. Kruglanski (eds.)
Social Psychology, pp.
133–68.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Hogan, R. (
1996). A socioanalytic perspective on the Five-Factor model. In
J. Wiggins (ed.)
The Five-Factor Model of Personality: Theoretical Perspectives, pp.
163–79.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Hoge, R. and
Renzulli, J. (
1993).
Exploring the link between giftedness and self-concept.
Review of Educational Research,
63(4),
499–65.
Google Scholar Hookway, C. (
2001). Epistemic akrasia and epistemic virtue. In
A. Fairweather and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, pp.
178–99.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Hookway, C. (
2003).
Affective states and epistemic immediacy.
Metaphilosophy,
34(1–2),
78–96.
Google Scholar Horgan, T. and
Tienson, J. (
1996).
Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Inan, I. (
2012).
The Philosophy of Curiosity.
Abingdon:
Routledge.
Google Scholar Inzlicht, M.,
Aronson, J.,
Good, C., and
McKay, L. (
2006).
A particular resiliency to threatening environments.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
42,
323–36.
Google Scholar Isen, A. M. and
Levin, P. F. (
1972).
Effect of feeling good on helping.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
21,
384–88.
Google Scholar Isen, A. M.,
DaubmanK., and
Nowicki, G. (
1987).
Positive affect facilitates creative problem solving.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
52(6),
1122–31.
Google Scholar Jenkins, C. S. (
2007a).
Entitlement and epistemic rationality.
Synthese,
157,
25–45.
Google Scholar Jenkins, C. S. (
2007b).
Epistemic norms and natural facts.
American Philosophical Quarterly,
44,
259–72.
Google Scholar Jenkins, C. S. (
2008a).
Grounding Concepts: An Empirical Basis for Arithmetical Knowledge.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Jenkins, C. S. (
2008b).
Boghossian and epistemic analyticity.
Croatian Journal of Philosophy,
8,
113–27.
Google Scholar Jenkins, C. S. (
2013). Naturalistic challenges to the a priori. In
A. Casullo and
J. Thurow (eds.)
The A Priori in Philosophy.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Jensen, A. (
1969).
How much can we boost IQ and scholastic achievement?Harvard Educational Review,
39,
1–123.
Google Scholar John, O. and
Robins, R. (
1994).
Traits and types, dynamics and development: no doors should be closed in the study of personality.
Psychological Inquiry,
5,
137–42.
Google Scholar John, O.,
Naumann, L., and
Soto, C. (
2008). Paradigm shift to the integrative Big Five trait taxonomy: history, measurement, and conceptual issues. In
O. John,
R. Robins, and
L. Pervin (eds.)
Handbook of Personality, Theory and Research, 3rd edn., pp.
114–58.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar Johns, M.,
Schmader, T., and
Martens, A. (
2005).
Knowing is half the battle: teaching stereotype threat as a means of improving women’s math performance.
Psychological Science,
16,
175–79.
Google Scholar Johnston, M. (
1996).
Is the external world invisible?Philosophical Issues,
7,
185–98.
Google Scholar Kahneman, D. (
2011).
Thinking Fast and Slow.
New York:
Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Google Scholar Kahneman, D. and
Frederick, S. (
2005). A model of heuristic judgment. In
K. Holyoak and
R. Morrison (eds.)
The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning, pp.
267–93.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Kahneman, D. and
Tversky, A. (
1973).
On the psychology of prediction.
Psychological Review,
80(4),
237–51.
Google Scholar Kalderon, M. E. (
2009).
Epistemic relativism.
Philosophical Review,
118(2),
225–40.
Google Scholar Kallestrup, J. and
Pritchard, D. H. (
2012).
Robust virtue epistemology and epistemic anti-individualism.
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly,
93,
84–103.
Google Scholar Kallestrup, J. and
Pritchard, D. H. (
2013). Robust virtue epistemology and epistemic dependence. In
T. Henning and
D. Schweikard (eds.)
Knowledge, Virtue and Action: Putting Epistemic Virtues to Work, pp.
209–26.
Abingdon:
Routledge.
Google Scholar Kallestrup, J. and
Pritchard, D. H. (In press).
Virtue epistemology and epistemic twin earth.
European Journal of Philosophy.
Google Scholar Kamtekar, Rachel. (
2004). “
Situationism and Virtue Ethics on the Content of Our Character.”
Ethics,
114 (April 2004):
458–491.
Google ScholarKanazawa, S. (
2008).
Temperature and evolutionary novelty as forces behind the evolution of general intelligence.
Intelligence,
36,
99–108.
Google Scholar Kappel, K. (
2010).
Expressivism about knowledge and the value of knowledge.
Acta Analytica,
25,
175–94.
Google Scholar Keifer, A. and
Sekaquaptewa, D. (
2007).
Implicit stereotypes and women’s math performance: how implicit gender-math stereotypes influence women’s susceptibility to stereotype threat.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
43,
825–32.
Google Scholar Kelly, T. (
2003).
Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: a critique.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
66,
612–40.
Google Scholar Kim, J. (
1988).
What is “naturalized epistemology”?Philosophical Perspectives,
2,
381–405.
Google Scholar Kitcher, P. (
1993).
The Advancement of Science: Science without Legend, Objectivity without Illusions.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Kornblith, H. (
1993).
Epistemic normativity.
Synthese,
94,
357–76.
Google Scholar Kornblith, H. (
2001). Epistemic obligation and the possibility of internalism. In
A. Fairweather and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, pp.
231–48.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Kornblith, H. (
2002).
Knowledge and its Place in Nature.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Kornblith, H. (
2010).
What reflective endorsement cannot do.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
80,
1–18.
Google Scholar Kornblith, H. (
2013).
On Reflection.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Korsgaard, C. M. (
1983).
Two distinctions in goodness.
Philosophical Review,
2,
169–95.
Google Scholar Korsgaard, C. M. (
1996).
The Sources of Normativity.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Korsgaard, C. M. (
2008). Aristotle’s function argument. In
The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology, pp.
129–50.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Kray, L.,
Thompson, L., and
Galinsky, A. (
2001).
Battle of the sexes: gender stereotype confirmation and reactance in negotiations.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
80,
942–58.
Google Scholar Kray, L.,
Galinsky, A., and
Thompson, L. (
2002).
Reversing the gender gap in negotiations: an exploration of stereotype regeneration.
Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes,
87,
386–409.
Google Scholar Kripke, S. (
1972).
Naming and Necessity.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Kvanvig, J. L. (
2003).
The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Langton, R. (
1993).
Speech acts and unspeakable acts.
Philosophy and Public Affairs,
22(4),
293–330.
Google Scholar Langton, R. (
1998).
Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Latane, B. and
J. M. Darley. (
1970).
The Unresponsive Bystander.
New York:
Appleton, Century, Crofts.
Google Scholar Leary, M. (
2004).
Introduction to Behavioral Research Methods, 4th edn.
Boston:
Pearson.
Google Scholar LeDoux, J. (
1996).
The Emotional Brain.
New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Google Scholar Lehrer, K. (
1990).
Theory of Knowledge.
Boulder, CO:
Westview.
Google Scholar Levy, B. (
1996).
Improving memory in old age through implicit self stereotyping.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
71,
1092–107.
Google Scholar Lewis, D. (
2008). Ramseyan humility. In
D. Braddon-Mitchell and
R. Nola (eds.)
Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, pp.
203–21.
Boston:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Lynch, M. P. (
2009a). The values of truth and the truth of values. In
A. Haddock,
A. Millar, and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
Epistemic Value, pp.
225–42.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Lynch, M. P. (
2009b).
Truth, value, and epistemic expressivism.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
79(1),
76–97.
Google Scholar Lyons, J. (
2011).
Response to critics.
Philosophical Studies,
153,
477–88.
Google Scholar McAdams, D. (
1992).
The Five-Factor model in personality: a critical appraisal.
Journal of Personality,
60,
329–61.
Google Scholar McAdams, D. (
1994).
A psychology of the stranger.
Psychological Inquiry,
5,
145–48.
Google Scholar McCauley, R. N. and
Henrich, J. (
2006).
Susceptibility to the Müller-Lyer illusion, theory-neutral observation, and the diachronic penetrability of the visual input system.
Philosophical Psychology,
19(1),
79–101. doi:
10.1080/09515080500462347.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. (
1994).
New goals for trait psychology.
Psychological Inquiry,
5,
148–53.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
1987).
Validation of the Five-Factor model of personality across instruments and observers.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
52,
81–90.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
1995).
Trait explanations in personality psychology.
European Journal of Personality,
9,
231–52.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
1996). Toward a new generation of personality theories: theoretical contexts for the Five-Factor model. In
J. Wiggins (ed.)
The Five-Factor Model of Personality: Theoretical Perspectives, pp.
51–87.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
1997).
Personality trait structure as a human universal.
American Psychologist,
52,
509–16.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
2003).
Personality in Adulthood: A Five-Factor Theory Perspective, 2nd edn.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
Costa, P. (
2008). The Five-Factor theory of personality. In
O. John,
R. Robins, and
L. Pervin (eds.)
Handbook of Personality: Theory and Research, 3rd edn., pp.
159–81.
New York:
The Guilford Press.
Google Scholar McCrae, R. and
John, O. (
1992).
An introduction to the Five-Factor model and its applications.
Journal of Personality,
60,
175–215.
Google Scholar McCrae, R.,
Costa, P.,
Ostenfdorf, F.,
Angleitner, A.,
Hřebíčková, M.,
Avia,
Sanz, J.,
Sánchez-Bernardos, M. L.,
Kusdil, M. E.,
Woodfield, R.,
Saunders, P. R., and
Smith, P. B. (
2000).
Nature over nurture: temperament, personality, and life span development.
Journal of Personal and Social Psychology,
78(1),
173–86.
Google Scholar MacFarlane, J. (
2005a).
Making sense of relative truth.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
105(1),
205–23.
Google Scholar MacFarlane, J. (
2005b).
The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions.
Oxford Studies in Epistemology,
1,
197–233.
Google Scholar McHugo, G. L.,
Lanzetta, J. T.,
Sullivan, D. G.,
Masters, R. D., and
Englis, B. G. (
1985).
Emotional reactions to a political leader’s expressive displays.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
49,
1513–29.
Google Scholar Mackie, J. L. (
1977).
Morality: Inventing Right and Wrong.
Harmondsworth, UK:
Penguin Books.
Google Scholar McLaughlin, P. (
2001).
What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Mallon, R. (
2004).
Passing, traveling and reality: social constructionism and the metaphysics of race.
Noûs,
38,4,
644–73.
CrossRef | Google Scholar Mallon, R. (
2006).
“Race”: normative, not metaphysical or semantic.
Ethics,
116(3),
525–51.
Google Scholar Mangels, J.,
Butterfield, B.,
Lamb, J.,
Good, C., and
Dweck, C. (
2006).
Why do beliefs about intelligence influence learning success? A social cognitive neuroscience model.
Social Cognition and Affective Neuroscience,
1(2),
75–86.
Google Scholar Mareschal, D. and
Johnson, S. P. (
2002).
Learning to perceive object unity: a connectionist account.
Developmental Science,
5(2),
151–85.
Google Scholar Martens, A.,
Johns, M.,
Greenberg, J., and
Schimel, J. (
2006).
Combating stereotype threat: the effect of self-affirmation on women’s intellectual performance.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
42,
236–43.
Google Scholar Marx, D. and
Goff, P. (
2005).
Clearing the air: the effect of experimenter race on target’s test performance and subjective experience.
British Journal of Social Psychology,
44,
645–57.
Google Scholar Mellor, D. H. (
1991). I and now. In
Matters of Metaphysics, pp.
17–30.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Merritt, M. (
2000).
Virtue ethics and situationist personality psychology.
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice,
3(4),
365–83.
Google Scholar Milgram, S. (
1974).
Obedience to Authority.
New York:
Harper & Row Publishers.
Google Scholar Millar, A. (
2008). Perceptual-recognitional abilities and perceptual knowledge. In
A. Haddock and
F. Macpherson (eds.)
Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, pp.
330–47.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Miller, C. (
2003).
Social psychology and virtue ethics.
Journal of Ethics,
7(4),
365–92.
Google Scholar Miller, C. (
2013).
Moral Character: An Empirical Theory.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Miller, C. (
2014).
Character and Moral Psychology.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Millikan, R. G. (
1984).
Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Mischel, W. (
1968).
Personality and Assessment.
New York:
John Wiley and Sons.
Google Scholar Mischel, W. (
2009).
From Personality and Assessment (1968) to personality science, 2009.
Journal of Research in Personality,
43,
282–90.
Google Scholar Mischel, W. and
Shoda, Y. (
1994).
Personality psychology has two goals: must it be two fields?Psychological Inquiry,
5,
156–58.
Google Scholar Mischel, W. and
Shoda, Y. (
1998).
Reconciling processing dynamics and personality dispositions.
Annual Review of Psychology,
49,
229–58.
Google Scholar Miyake, A.,
Kost-Smith, L.,
Finkelstein, N.,
Pollock, S.,
Cohen, G., and
Ito, T. (
2010).
Reducing the gender achievement gap in college science: a classroom study of values affirmation.
Science,
330,
1234–37.
Google Scholar Montmarquet, J. (
1993).
Epistemic Virtue and Doxastic Responsibility.
Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield.
Google Scholar Moore, G. E. (
1993).
Principia ethica, ed.
T. Baldwin.
Cambridge University Press (first published 1903).
Google Scholar Morsella, E. and
Bargh, J. A. (
2010).
What is an output?Psychological Inquiry,
21,
354–70.
Google Scholar Mount, M. and
Barrick, M. (
1998).
Five reasons why the “Big Five” article has been frequently cited.
Personnel Psychology,
51,
849–57.
Google Scholar Nanay, B. (
2012).
Success semantics: the sequel.
Philosophical Studies,
1(15),
151–65.
Google Scholar Neta, R. (
2007). How to naturalize epistemology. In
V. F. Hendricks and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
New Waves in Epistemology, pp.
324–53.
Basingstoke, UK:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar Nettle, D. (
2007).
Personality: What Makes You the Way You Are.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Nguyen, H.-H. D. and
Ryan, A. M. (
2008).
Does stereotype threat affect test performance of minorities and women? A meta-analysis of experimental evidence.
Journal of Applied Psychology,
93,
1314–34.
Google Scholar Nozick, R. (
1981).
Philosophical Explanations.
Cambridge, MA:
Belknap Press.
Google Scholar Nussbaum, M. (
1986).
The Fragility of Goodness.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Nussbaum, M. (
2001).
Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of the Emotions.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Nussbaum, M. (
2003). Emotions as judgments of value and importance. In
R. C. Solomon (ed.)
What Is an Emotion?, pp.
271–83.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Olson, J. (
2011). Error theory and reasons for belief. In
A. Reisner and
A. Seglich-Petersen (eds.)
Reasons for Belief, pp.
75–93.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Owens, D. (
2003).
Does belief have an aim?Philosophical Studies,
115,
283–305.
Google Scholar Ozer, D. and
Benet-Martínez, V. (
2006).
Personality and the prediction of consequential outcome.
Annual Review of Psychology,
57,
401–21.
Google Scholar Ozer, D. and
Reise, S. (
1994). Personality assessment. In
L. Porter and
M. Rosenzweig (eds.)
Annual Review of Psychology, vol.
xlv, pp.
357–88.
Palo Alto, CA:
Annual Reviews.
Google Scholar Pamental, M. (
2010).
Dewey, situationism, and moral education.
Educational Theory,
60(2),
147–66.
Google Scholar Papineau, D. (
1999).
Normativity and judgment.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
73,
16–43.
Google Scholar Paunonen, S. and
Jackson, D. (
2000).
What is beyond the Big Five?Journal of Personality,
68,
821–35.
Google Scholar Pervin, L. (
1994).
A critical analysis of current trait theory.
Psychological Inquiry,
5,
103–13.
Google Scholar Piedmont, R. (
1998).
The Revised NEO Personality Inventory: Clinical and Research Applications.
New York:
Plenum Press.
Google Scholar Pinker, S. (
1997).
How the Mind Works.
New York:
Norton.
Google Scholar Plato (
1989).
Protagoras. In
Collected Dialogues, ed.
E. Hamilton.
Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Price, C. (
2006). Fearing Fluffy: the content of an emotional appraisal. In
G. Macdonald and
D. Papineau (eds.)
Teleosemantics, pp.
208–28.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Prinz, J. (
2004).
Gut Reactions.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Prinz, J. (
2009).
The normativity challenge: cultural psychology provides the real threat to virtue ethics.
Journal of Ethics,
13,
117–44.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2007).
Recent work on epistemic value.
American Philosophical Quarterly,
44,
85–110.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2009a).
Apt performance and epistemic value.
Philosophical Studies,
143,
407–16.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2009b). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. In
A. O’Hear (ed.)
Epistemology, pp.
19–43. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2009c).
Knowledge.
Basingstoke, UK:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2009d).
The value of knowledge.
Harvard Review of Philosophy,
16,
2–19.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2012).
Anti-luck virtue epistemology.
Journal of Philosophy,
109(3),
247–79.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (
2013).
Epistemic virtue and the epistemology of education.
Journal of Philosophy of Education,
47 (2013),
236–47.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. (In press b). The situationist challenge, epistemic dependence, and the epistemology of education. In
A. Fairweather and
A. Alfano (eds.)
Epistemic Situationism.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H. and
Smith, M. (
2004).
The psychology and philosophy of luck.
New Ideas in Psychology,
22,
1–28.
Google Scholar Pritchard, D. H.,
Millar, A., and
Haddock, A. (
2010).
The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Putnam, H. (
1975). The meaning of “meaning.” In
Philosophical Papers, vol.
ii,
Mind, Language, and Reality, pp.
215–72.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Pytlik Zillig, L.,
Hemenover, S., and
Dienstbier, R. (
2002).
What do we assess when we assess a Big 5 trait? A content analysis of the affective, behavioral, and cognitive processes represented in Big 5 personality inventories.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
28,
847–58.
Google Scholar Quine, W. V. O. (
1969). Epistemology naturalized. In
Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, pp.
69–90.
New York:
Columbia University Press.
Google Scholar Quine, W. V. O. (
1986). Reply to Morton White. In
L. Hahn and
P. Schlipp (eds.)
The Philosophy of W. V. O. Quine, pp.
663–65.
La Salle, IL:
Open Court.
Google Scholar Railton, P. (
1986).
Moral realism.
Philosophical Review,
95,
163–207.
Google Scholar Railton, P. (
1997). On the hypothetical and non-hypothetical in reasoning about belief and action. In
G. Cullity and
B. Gaut (eds.)
Ethics and Practical Reason, pp.
53–79.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Ramsey, F. P. (
1927).
Facts and propositions.
Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes,
7,
153–70.
Google Scholar Ramsey, F. P. (
1931). Knowledge. In
The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, ed.
R. B. Braithwaite, pp.
258–59.
New York:
Harcourt Brace.
Google Scholar Rattan, A.,
Good, C., and
Dweck, C. (
2012).
“It’s OK – not everyone can be good at math”: instructors with an entity theory comfort (and demotivate) students.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
48,
731–37.
Google Scholar Reisner, A. (
2008).
Weighing pragmatic and evidential reasons for belief.
Philosophical Studies,
138,
17–27.
Google Scholar Reisner, A. (
2009).
The possibility of pragmatic reasons for belief and the wrong kind of reason problem.
Philosophical Studies,
145(2),
257–72.
Google Scholar Ridge, M. (
2011).
Getting lost on the road to Larissa.
Noûs,
47(1),
181–201.
Google Scholar Riggs, W. (
2007). The value turn in epistemology. In
V. F. Hendricks and
D. Pritchard (eds.)
New Waves in Epistemology, pp.
300–23.
Basingstoke, UK:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar Riggs, W. (
2009). Understanding, knowledge, and the
Meno requirement. In
A. Haddock,
A. Millar, and
D. H. Pritchard (eds.)
Epistemic Value, pp.
331–38.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Rist, R. (
1973).
The Urban School: A Factory for Failure.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Roberts, B. (
2009).
Back to the future: Personality and Assessment and personality development.
Journal of Research in Personality,
43,
137–45.
Google Scholar Roberts, R. and
Wood, W. J. (
2007).
Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology.
Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Robertson, E. (
2009). The epistemic aims of education. In
H. Siegel (ed.)
The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education, pp.
11–34.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Rosenthal, H.,
Crisp, R., and
Suen, M.-W. (
2007).
Improving performance expectancies in stereotypic domains: task relevance and the reduction of stereotype threat.
European Journal of Social Psychology,
37,
586–97.
Google Scholar Ruse, M. (
1971).
Functional statements in biology.
Philosophy of Science,
38,
87–95.
Google Scholar Russell, D. C. (
2009).
Practical Intelligence and the Virtues.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Ryan, S. (
1999).
What is wisdom?Philosophical Studies,
93,
119–39.
Google Scholar Salmon, W. C. (
1998).
Causality and Explanation.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Samuels, R.,
Stich, S., and
Bishop, M. (
2002). Ending the rationality wars: how to make disputes about human rationality disappear. In
R. Elio (ed.)
Common Sense, Reasoning, and Rationality, pp.
236–68.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Sánchez-Bernardos, M. (
2000).
Nature over nurture: temperament, personality, and life span development.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
7(8),
173–86.
Google Scholar Schimel, J.,
Arndt, J.,
Banko, K., and
Cook, A. (
2004).
Not all self-affirmations were created equal: the cognitive and social benefits of affirming the intrinsic (vs. extrinsic) self.
Social Cognition,
22,
75–99.
Google Scholar Schmader, T. and
Johns, M. (
2003).
Converging evidence that stereotype threat reduces working memory capacity.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
85(3),
440–52.
Google Scholar Schmader, T.,
Johns, M., and
Barquissau, M. (
2004).
The costs of accepting gender differences: the role of stereotype endorsement in women’s experience in the math domain.
Sex Roles,
50,
835–50.
Google Scholar Schueler, G. F. (
1995).
Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action.
Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Google Scholar Searle, J. (
1969).
Speech Acts.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Segall, M. H.,
Campbell, D. T., and
Herskovits, M. J. (
1966).
The Influence of Culture on Visual Perception.
Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill Co.
Google Scholar Shah, N. (
2003).
How truth governs belief.
Philosophical Review,
112,
447–82.
Google Scholar Shah, N. (
2006).
A new argument for evidentialism.
Philosophical Quarterly,
56,
481–98.
Google Scholar Shah, N. (
2011). Can reasons for belief be debunked? In
A. Reisner and
A. Steglich-Petersen (eds.)
Reasons for Belief, pp.
94–107.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Shah, N. and
Velleman, J. D. (
2005).
Doxastic deliberation.
Philosophical Review,
114,
497–534.
Google Scholar Sherman, N. (
1989).
The Fabric of Character.
New York:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Shih, M.,
Pittinsky, T. L., and
Ambady, N. (
1999).
Stereotype susceptibility: identity salience and shifts in quantitative performance.
Psychological Science,
10,
80–83.
Google Scholar Shiota, M.,
Keltner, D., and
Mossman, A. (
2007).
The nature of awe: elicitors, appraisals, and effects on self-concept.
Cognition and Emotion,
21(5),
944–63.
Google Scholar Sider, T. (
2009). Ontological realism. In
D. Chalmers,
D. Manley, and
R. Wasserman (eds.)
Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, pp.
384–423.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Sider, T. (
2011).
Writing the Book of the World.
Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Slingerland, E. (
2011).
The situationist critique and early Confucian virtue ethics.
Ethics,
121(2),
390–419.
Google Scholar Smith, P. (
2003). Deflationism: the facts. In
H. Lillehammer and
G. Rodriguez-Pereyra (eds.)
Real Metaphysics, pp.
43–52.
New York:
Routledge.
Google Scholar Snow, N. E. (
2010).
Virtue as Social Intelligence: An Empirically Grounded Theory.
Abingdon:
Routledge.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
1988).
Beyond skepticism, to the best of our knowledge.
Mind,
97,
153–89.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
1991).
Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
1993).
Proper functionalism and virtue epistemology.
Noûs,
27(1),
51–65.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2003). The place of truth in epistemology. In
M. DePaul and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, pp.
155–79.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2007).
A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, vol.
i.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2009a).
Knowing full well: the normativity of beliefs as performances.
Philosophical Studies,
142,
5–15.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2009b).
Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, vol.
ii.
Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2009c). Situations against virtues: the situationist attack on virtue theory. In
C. Mantzavinos (ed.)
Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, pp.
274–90.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Sosa, E. (
2010).
Knowing Full Well.
Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Spencer, S.,
Steele, C., and
Quinn, D. (
1999).
Stereotype threat and women’s math performance.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
35,
4–28.
Google Scholar Sreenivasan, G. (
2002).
Errors about errors: virtue theory and trait attribution.
Mind,
111,
47–68.
Google Scholar Stangor, C.,
Carr, C., and
Kiang, L. (
1998).
Activating stereotypes undermines task performance expectations.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
75,
1191–97.
Google Scholar Stanley, J. (
2005)
Knowledge and Practical Interests.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Steele, C. M. and
Aronson, J. (
1995).
Stereotype threat and the intellectual test performance of African-Americans.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
69,
797–811.
Google Scholar Steglich-Petersen, A. (
2006).
No norm needed: on the aim of belief.
Philosophical Quarterly,
56,
499–516.
Google Scholar Steglich-Petersen, A. (
2009).
Weighing the aim of belief.
Philosophical Studies,
145(3),
395–405.
Google Scholar Steglich-Petersen, A. (
2011). How to be a teleologist about epistemic reasons. In
A. Reisner and
A. Steglich-Petersen (eds.)
Reasons for Belief, pp.
13–33.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Stone, J. (
2002).
Battling doubt by avoiding practice: the effect of stereotype threat on self-handicapping in white athletes.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
28,
1667–78.
Google Scholar Stone, J.,
Lynch, C.,
Sjomeling, M., and
Darley, J. (
1999).
Stereotype threat effects on black and white athletic performance.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
77,
1213–27.
Google Scholar Stöttinger, E. and
Perner, J. (
2006).
Dissociating size representation for action and for conscious judgment: grasping visual illusions without apparent obstacles.
Consciousness and Cognition,
15(2),
269–84.
Google Scholar Strack, F.,
Martin, L. L., and
Stepper, S. (
1988).
Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the human smile.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
54,
768–76.
Google Scholar Strandberg, C. (
2011).
A dual aspect account of moral language.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
84(1),
87–122.
Google Scholar Sturgeon, N. (
1985). Moral explanations. In
D. Copp and
D. Zimmerman (eds.)
Morality, Reason and Truth, pp.
49–78.
Totowa, NJ:
Rowman and Allenfeld.
Google Scholar Templer, D. (
2008).
Correlational and factor analytic support for Rushton’s differential K life history theory.
Personality and Individual Differences,
45,
440–44.
Google Scholar Templer, D. and
Arikawa, H. (
2006).
Temperature, skin color, per capita income, and IQ: an international perspective.
Intelligence,
34,
121–39.
Google Scholar Treanor, N. (In press).
The measure of knowledge.
Noûs 47(3), pp.
577–601.
Google Scholar Turri, J. (
2011).
Manifest failure: the Gettier problem solved.
Philosophers’ Imprint,
11(8),
1–11.
Google Scholar Tversky, A. and
Kahneman, D. (
1973).
Availability: a heuristic for judging frequency and probability.
Cognitive Psychology,
5,
207–32.
Google Scholar Tversky, A. and
Kahneman, D. (
2002). Extensional
versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. In
T. Gilovich,
D. Griffin, and
D. Kahneman (eds.)
Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, pp.
19–48.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Velleman, D. (
2000). On the aim of belief. In
J. Velleman (ed.)
The Possibility of Practical Reason, pp.
244–81.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Vogel, J. (
2000).
Reliabilism leveled.
Journal of Philosophy,
97,
602–23.
Google Scholar Walton, G. and
Cohen, G. (
2003).
Stereotype lift.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
39,
456–67.
Google Scholar Wason, P. (
1966). Reasoning. In
B. M. Foss (ed.)
New Horizons in Psychology, pp.
135–51.
Harmondsworth, UK:
Penguin Books.
Google Scholar Wedgwood, R. (
2002).
The aim of belief.
Philosophical Perspectives,
16,
265–97.
Google Scholar Whitcomb, D. (
2010).
Curiosity was framed.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
81(3),
664–87.
Google Scholar White, R. (
2007).
Epistemic subjectivism.
Episteme,
4(1),
115–29.
Google Scholar Whyte, J. T. (
1990).
Success semantics.
Analysis,
50,
149–57.
Google Scholar Widiger, T. (
1993).
The DSM-III-R categorical personality disorder diagnoses: a critique and an alternative.
Psychological Inquiry,
4,
75–90.
Google Scholar Wiggins, J. and
Trapnell, P. (
1997). Personality structure: the return of the Big Five. In
R. Hogan,
J. Johnson, and
S. Briggs (eds.)
Handbook of Personality Psychology, pp.
737–65.
San Diego:
Academic Press.
Google Scholar Williams, B. (
1995). Internal reasons and the obscurity of blame. In
Making Sense of Humanity, pp.
35–45.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Williams, B. (
2002).
Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy.
Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Wolterstorff, N. (
2010). Ought to believe: two concepts. In
T. Cuneo (ed.)
Practices of Belief, pp.
62–85.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Wooldridge, D. (
1963).
Machinery of the Brain.
New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Google Scholar Wright, C. (
2004).
On epistemic entitlement: warrant for nothing (and foundations for free?).
Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes,
78,
167–212.
Google Scholar Wright, L. (
1973).
Functions.
Philosophical Review,
82,
139–68.
Google Scholar Wright, L. (
2012). Revisiting teleological explanations: reflections three decades on. In
P. Huneman (ed.)
Functions: Selection and Mechanisms, pp.
233–43. Synthese Library 363.
Dordrecht, the Netherlands:
Springer.
Google Scholar Yeung, N. and von
Hippel, C. (
2008).
Stereotype threat increases the likelihood that female drivers in a simulator run over jaywalkers.
Accident Analysis and Prevention,
40,
667–74.
Google Scholar Zagzebski, L. T. (
1996).
Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Zagzebski, L. (
1999). What is knowledge? In
J. Greco and
E. Sosa (eds.)
The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, pp.
92–116.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
Google Scholar Zagzebski, L. (
2001). Must knowers be agents? In
A. Fairweather and
L. Zagzebski (eds.)
Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, pp.
142–57.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Zagzebski, L. (
2004).
Epistemic value and the primacy of what we care about.
Philosophical Papers,
33(3),
353–77.
Google Scholar Zagzebski, L. (
2012).
Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief.
Oxford University Press.
Google Scholar Zajonc, R. B. (
1980).
Feeling and thinking: preferences need no inferences.
American Psychologist,
35(2),
151–75.
Google Scholar Zajonc, R. B. (
1984).
On the primacy of affect.
American Psychologist,
39(2),
117–23.
Google Scholar Zajonc, R. B. (
2000). Feeling and thinking: closing the debate over the independence of affect. In
J. P. Forgas (ed.)
Feeling and Thinking, pp.
31–58.
Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar Zimbardo, P. G. (
1992).
Quiet Rage: The Stanford Prison Experiment (DVD). Stanford Instructional Television Network.
Google Scholar