Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T08:54:09.848Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 July 2023

Lloyd P. Gerson
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Plato's Moral Realism , pp. 228 - 249
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

All citations from Plato are from the five-volume Oxford Classical Texts Plato (OCT), edited by Burnet, John, Platonis opera, Oxford, 1900–1907 with the Addition of Platonis Rempublicam, edited by Slings, S. R. (Oxford, 2003) and Platonis opera, Tetralogias I–II, edited by Duke, E. A, Hicke, W. F., Nicoll, W. S. M., Robinson, D. B., and Strachan, J. C. G. (Oxford, 1995).Google Scholar
All citations from Aristotle are from the OCT editions of Aristotle.Google Scholar
Alcinous, . Enseignement des doctrines de Platon (Didaskalilos), edited by Whittaker, J.. Paris, 2002.Google Scholar
Atticus, . Fragments, edited by des Places, É. Paris, 1977.Google Scholar
Iamblichus, . Les mystères d’Égypt, edited by des Places, É. Paris, 1966.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. (ed.). Aristotelis Metaphysica. Oxford, 1957.Google Scholar
Plotinus, . Plotini opera, 3 volumes, edited by Henry, P. and Schwyzer, R.. Oxford, 1964–1983.Google Scholar
Proclus, . Elements of Theology, 2nd ed., edited by Dodds, E. R.. Oxford, 1963.Google Scholar
Proclus, In Platonis rem publicam, 2 volumes, edited by Kroll, W.. Leipzig, 1899–1901.Google Scholar
Proclus, In Platonis Parmenidem commentaria, 3 volumes, edited by Steel, C.. Oxford, 2007–2009.Google Scholar
Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum commentaria, 3 volumes, edited by Diehl, E.. Leipzig, 1903–1906.Google Scholar
Proclus, Sur le premier Alcibiade de Platon, 2 volumes, edited by Segonds, A.-P.. Paris, 1985–1986.Google Scholar
Proclus, Théologie platonicienne, 6 volumes, edited by Saffrey, H. D. and Westerink, L. G.. Paris, 1968–1997.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (ed.) Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 2 vols. Oxford, 1924.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Adam, J. A. 1921. The Republic of Plato, with critical notes, commentary, and appendices. 2 vols. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Adams, R. 1983. “Divine Necessity.” The Journal of Philosophy 80: 741752.Google Scholar
Adams, R. 1999. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford.Google Scholar
Ademollo, F. 2018. “On Plato’s Conception of Change.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 55: 3583.Google Scholar
Allan, D. J. 1955. “Plato’s Moral Philosophy.” Classical Review 5(1): 5356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, A. 1969. “Socratic Reasoning in the Euthyphro.” Review of Metaphysics 22: 6176.Google Scholar
Anderson, M. 2020. “What Are the Wages of Justice? Rethinking the Republic’s Division of Goods.” Phronesis 65: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1993. “Virtue as the Use of Other Goods.” In Virtue, Love and Form: Essays in Memory of Gregory Vlastos, edited by Irwin, T. and Nussbaum, M. (= Apeiron 25, 3/4). Edmonton, AL: 5366.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1997. “Understanding the Good: Sun, Line, and Cave.” In Plato’s Republic: Critical Essays, edited by Kraut, R.. Lanham, MD: 143168.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1999. Platonic Ethics: Old and New. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 2008. “Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism.” In Morality and Self-Interest, edited by Bloomfield, P.. Oxford: 205221.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 2011. “Plato’s Ethics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Plato, edited by Fine, G.. Oxford: 267285.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 2015. “Plato’s Defense of Justice: The Wrong Kind of Reason?” In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, edited by Rabbas, O., Emilsson, E., Fossheim, H., and Tuominen, M.. Oxford: 4965.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1958. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy 33: 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, E. 2000. Intention, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Apelt, O. 1912. “Das Prinzip der platonischen Ethik.” In Platonische Aufsätze. Leipzig: 109120.Google Scholar
Archer-Hind, R. D. (ed.) 1888. The Timaeus of Plato. With introduction and notes. London.Google Scholar
Ayers, M. (ed.) 2007. Rationalism, Platonism, and God. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, S. 2017. “The Metaphysics of Goodness in the Ethics of Aristotle.” Philosophical Studies 174: 18391856.Google Scholar
Baker, S. 2021. “A Monistic Conclusion to Aristotle’s Ergon Argument: The Human Good as the Best Achievement of a Human.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103(3): 373403.Google Scholar
Baracchi, C. 2008. Aristotle’s Ethics as First Philosophy. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Baracchi, C. 2014. “One Good: The Mathematics of Ethics.” Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 25(2): 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baras, D. 2017. “A Reliability Challenge to Theistic Platonism.” Analysis 77: 479487.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 1998. “Commentary on Rist: Is Plato Interested in Meta-Ethics?Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 14: 7381.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2010a. “Notes on Plato on the Kalon and the Good.” Classical Philology 105: 363377.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2010b. “Plato on the Desire for the Good.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives, edited by Tenenbaum, S.. Oxford: 3464.Google Scholar
Becker, L. 1998. A New Stoicism. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Bedke, M. 2009. “Intuitive Non-Naturalism Meets Cosmic Coincidence.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90: 188209.Google Scholar
Beere, J. 2011. “Philosophy, Virtue, and Immortality in Plato’s Phaedo.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 26: 253288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beierwaltes, W. 2002. “Das Eine als Norm des Lebens. Zum metaphysischen Grund Neuplatonischer Lebensform.” In Metaphysik und Religion: Zur Signatur des Spätantiken Denkens, edited by Kobusch, T. and Erler, M.. Leipzig: 121151.Google Scholar
Benitez, E. E. 1995. “The Good or the Demiurge: Causation and the Unity of the Good in Plato.” Apeiron 28: 113140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, H. J. 2000. Socratic Wisdom. Oxford.Google Scholar
Benson, H. J. (ed.). 2006. A Companion to Plato. Malden, MA.Google Scholar
Berman, S. 2003. “A Defense of Psychological Egoism.” In Desire, Identity and Existence, edited by Reshotko, N. Kelowna, BC: 143157.Google Scholar
Berti, E. 1983. “Il Platone di Krämer e la metafisica classica.” Rivista di filosofia neoscolastica 75: 313326.Google Scholar
Berti, E. 2004. “Is There an Ethics in Plato’s ‘Unwritten Doctrines’?” In Plato Ethicus: Philosophy Is Life. Proceedings of the International Colloquium Piacenza, edited by Migliori, M. and Napolitano, L.. Sankt Augustin: 3548.Google Scholar
Berti, E. 2017. Aristotele: Metafisica. Bari.Google Scholar
Blackson, T. 2015. “Two Interpretations of Socratic Intellectualism.” Ancient Philosophy 35(1): 2339.Google Scholar
Blanshard, B. 1961. Reason and Goodness. London.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 1991. “Persuasion, Compulsion, and Freedom in Plato’s Laws.” Classical Quarterly 41: 365388.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 1995a. “Plato’s Theory of Goods in the Laws and Philebus.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 11: 101139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C. 1995b. “The Virtues of Ordinary People in Plato’s Statesman.” In Reading the Statesman: Proceedings of the III Symposium Platonicum, edited by Rowe, C.. Sankt Augustin: 313329.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2002. Plato’s Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C. (ed.) 2017. The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics. Cambridge, UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodéüs, R. 1992. Aristote et la théologie des vivants immortels. St-Laurent, PQ.Google Scholar
Bonazzi, M. 2013. “Il posto dell’ etica nel sistema del platonismo.” In Ethik des antiken Platonismus, edited by Pietsch, C.. Stuttgart: 2533.Google Scholar
Bordt, M. 2006. Platons Theologie. Munich.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 1988. “How to Be a Moral Realist.” In Essays on Moral Realism, edited by Sayre-McCord, G.. Ithaca, NY: 181228.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 2003a. “Finite Beings, Finite Goods: The Semantics, Metaphysics and Ethics of Naturalist Consequentialism, Part 1.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 505553.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 2003b. “Finite Beings, Finite Goods: The Semantics, Metaphysics and Ethics of Naturalist Consequentialism, Part 2.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67: 2447.Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G. 2014. “Unity and the Good: Platonists Against οἰκείωσις.” In Unité et origine des vertus dans la philosophie ancienne, edited by Collette-Dučić, B. and Delcomminette, S.. Brussels: 297320.Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G. 2018. Platonist Philosophy 80BC to AD 250: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Bradley, F. H. 1876 [1927]. “Why Should I Be Moral?” In Ethical Studies. London: 5884.Google Scholar
Brenner, A. 2018. “Theism and Explanationist Defenses of Moral Realism.” Faith and Philosophy 35(4): 447463.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. 1979. “Plato’s Moral Theory.” New Scholasticism 53(3): 529535.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 1987. “Socrates on Goods, Virtue, and Happiness.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 5: 127.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 1994. Plato’s Socrates. Oxford.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 2000. The Philosophy of Socrates. Boulder, CO.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 2002. “Incurable Souls in Socratic Psychology.” Ancient Philosophy 22: 2136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 2006. “The Socratic Paradoxes.” In A Companion to Plato, edited by Benson, H.. Malden, MA: 263277.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 2007. “Socrates on Akrasia, Knowledge, and the Power of Appearance.” In Akrasia in Greek Philosophy, edited by Destrée, P. and Bobonich, C.. Leiden: 117.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. D. 2010. Socratic Moral Psychology. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Brink, D. 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundation of Ethics. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Brisson, L. 2018. “Sur le Bien: Métamorphose d’une anecdote.” Χώρα 16: 167180.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1959. Five Types of Ethical Theory. Paterson, NJ.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 2001. “Theodicy and Pseudo-History in the Timaeus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 21: 128.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 2021. Plato’s Sun-Like Good: Dialectic in the Republic. Cambridge, UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2012. “The Unity of the Soul in Plato’s Republic.” In Plato and the Divided Self, edited by Barney, R., Brennan, T., and Brittain, C.. Cambridge, UK: 5373.Google Scholar
Brown, L. 2007. “Glaucon’s Challenge, Rational Egoism and Ordinary Morality.” In Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, D., Hermann, F. G., and Penner, T.. Edinburgh: 4260.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, J. 1971. “EE 18, 1218a15-31 et le περὶ τάγαθοῦ.” In Untersuchungen zur Eudemischen Ethik, edited by Moraux, P.. Berlin: 197222.Google Scholar
Burkert, W. 1972. Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Cambridge, MA. (Translation of 1962, Weisheit und Wissenschaft: Studien zu Pythagoras, Philoloaus und Platon, Nuremberg.)Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 1999. “Culture and Society in Plato’s Republic.” The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 22: 215324.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2000. “Plato on Why Mathematics Is Good for the Soul.” In Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy, edited by Smiley, T.. Oxford: 181.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2006. “The Truth of Tripartition.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106: 123.Google Scholar
Bury, R. G. 1910. “The Ethics of Plato.” The International Journal of Ethics 20(3): 271281.Google Scholar
Butchvarov, P. 1989. Skepticism in Ethics. Bloomington, IN.Google Scholar
Butler, T. 2019. “Refining Motivational Intellectualism: Plato’s Protagoras and Phaedo.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 101(2): 153176.Google Scholar
Cairns, D., Hermann, F.-G., and Penner, T. (eds.). 2007. Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic. Edinburgh.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callard, A. 2014. “Ignorance and Akrasia-Denial in the Protagoras.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 3180.Google Scholar
Callard, A. 2016. “Acratics as Hedonists: Protagoras 352B-355A.” Ancient Philosophy 36(1): 4764.Google Scholar
Callard, A. 2017. “Everyone Desires the Good: Socrates’ Protreptic Theory.” Review of Metaphysics 70: 617644.Google Scholar
Campbell, D. 2022The Soul’s Tomb: Plato on the Body as the Cause of Psychic Disorders.” Apeiron 55(1): 119139.Google Scholar
Carone, G. 1994. “Teleology and Evil in Laws 10.” Review of Metaphysics 48(2): 275298.Google Scholar
Carone, G. 2001. “Akrasia in the Republic: Does Plato Change His Mind?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20: 107148.Google Scholar
Carone, G. 2004. “Calculating Machines or Leaky Jars? The Moral Psychology of Plato’s Gorgias.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 23: 5596.Google Scholar
Carone, G. 2005a. “Mind and Body in Late Plato.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 87: 227269.Google Scholar
Carone, G. 2005b. Plato’s Cosmology and Its Ethical Dimensions. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Cartledge, P. 2000. The Greeks: Crucible of Civilization. Oxford.Google Scholar
Catana, L. 2019. Late Ancient Platonism in Eighteenth-Century Thought. Cham.Google Scholar
Centrone, B. 2003. “Platonic Virtue as a Holon: From the Laws to the Protagoras.” In Plato Ethicus: Philosophy Is Life. Proceedings of the International Colloquium Piacenza, edited by Migliori, M. and Napolitano, L.. Sankt Augustin: 93106.Google Scholar
Centrone, B. 2021. La seconda polis: Introduzione alle Leggi di Platone. Rome.Google Scholar
Chambers, L. P. 1936. “Plato’s Objective Standard of Value.” Journal of Philosophy 33(22): 596605.Google Scholar
Chan, B. 2021. “A Platonic Kind-Based Account of Goodness.” Philosophia 49(4): 13691389.Google Scholar
Chappell, T. 1993. “The Virtues of Thrasymachus.” Phronesis 38: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, T. 2008. “Moral Perception.” Philosophy 83, 4: 421437.Google Scholar
Chappell, T. 2010. “Euthyphro’s ‘Dilemma,’ Socrates’ Daimonion, and Plato’s God.” European Journal of Philosophy 1: 3964.Google Scholar
Chappell, T. 2014. Knowing What to Do: Imagination, Virtue, and Platonism in Ethics. Oxford.Google Scholar
Cheney, D. R. 1971. Broad’s Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy. London.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. 1971 [1954]. “The Sources of Evil According to Plato.” In Plato II, edited by Vlastos, G.. Garden City, NJ: 244258.Google Scholar
Chilcott, C. M. 1923. “The Platonic Theory of Evil.” Classical Quarterly 17(1): 2734.Google Scholar
Chlup, R. 2012. Proclus: An Introduction. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Clark, J. 2012. “The Strength of Knowledge in Plato’s Protagoras.” Ancient Philosophy 32(2): 237255.Google Scholar
Clark-Doane, J. 2012. “Morality and Mathematics: The Evolutionary Challenge.” Ethics 122: 313340.Google Scholar
Cook, A. B. 1896. The Metaphysical Basis of Plato’s Ethics. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1977. “The Psychology of Justice in Plato.” American Philosophical Quarterly 14: 151157. (Reprinted in 1999, Reason and Emotion. Princeton, NJ: 138149.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1984. “Plato’s Theory of Human Motivation.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 321. (Reprinted in 1999, Reason and Emotion. Princeton, NJ: 118137.)Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1999 [1984]. Reason and Emotion. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. 1923. Greek Religious Thought. London.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. 1937. Plato’s Cosmology. London.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 2006. Reason and the Good. Oxford.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. (ed.) 2013. The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crombie, I. M. 1962. An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines, Vol. I. New York.Google Scholar
Cross, R. C. and Woozley, A .D. 1964. Plato’s Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2004. Ethics without Principles. Oxford.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, S. 2017. “Non-naturalism and Normative Authority.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 117(3): 297313.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1993. “Plato’s Philosopher.” In Virtue, Love and Form: Essays in Memory of Gregory Vlastos, edited by Irwin, T. and Nussbaum, M. (= Apeiron 25, 3/4). Edmonton, AL: 175194.Google Scholar
De Sousa, R. 1974. “The Good and the True.” Mind 83: 534551.Google Scholar
De Strycker, E. 1970. “L’Idée du Bien dans la République de Platon: Données philologiques et signification philosophique.” L’antiquité classique 39: 450467.Google Scholar
De Vogel, C. 1986. Rethinking Plato and Platonism. Leiden.Google Scholar
Deigh, J. 2018. From Psychology to Morality: Essays in Ethical Naturalism. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delcomminette, S. 2006. Le Philèbe de Platon: Introduction à l’Agathologie platonicienne. Leiden.Google Scholar
Demos, R. 1967. “Plato on Moral Principles.” Mind 76(301): 125126.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. 2007. “Sun and Line: The Role of the Good.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, edited by Ferrari, G.. Cambridge, UK: 284309.Google Scholar
Desjardins, R. 2004. Plato on the Good. Leiden.Google Scholar
Despland, M. 1985. The Education of Desire: Plato and the Philosophy of Religion. Toronto.Google Scholar
Destrée, P. 2017. “How Does Contemplation Make You Happy?” In Plato: Symposium. A Critical Guide, edited by Destrée, P. and Giannopolou, Z.. Cambridge, UK: 216234.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 1992. “The Unity of the Virtues in Plato’s Protagoras and Laches.” Philosophical Review 101: 765789.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 1995. “Socrates’ Kantian Conception of Virtue.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 33: 381408.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 2008. “Socratic Ethics and Moral Psychology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Plato, edited by Fine, G.. Oxford: 139164.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 2017. “Virtue and Happiness in Plato.” In The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics, edited by Bobonich, C.. Cambridge, UK: 5271.Google Scholar
Diès, A. 1927. Autour de Platon. 2 vols. Paris.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. 2003. The Heirs of Plato. Oxford.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. 2013. “The Hierarchy of Being as Framework for Platonic Ethical Theory.” In Ethik des Antiken Platonismus, edited by Pietsch, C.. Stuttgart: 9198.Google Scholar
Dodds, E. R. 1959. Plato: Gorgias. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford.Google Scholar
Dorter, K. 1994. Form and Good in Plato’s Eleatic Dialogues. Berkeley.Google Scholar
Dorter, K. 2006. The Transformation of Plato’s Republic. Lanham, MD.Google Scholar
Drefcinski, S. 2014. “What Does It Mean to Become Like God? Theaetetus 176A–177B.” International Philosophical Quarterly 54(4): 411427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreier, J. 1992. “The Supervenience Argument against Moral Realism.The Southern Journal of Philosophy 30: 1338.Google Scholar
Dreier, J. 1993. “The Structure of Normative Theories.” Monist 76(1): 2240.Google Scholar
Duffy, H. 2020. “Rules for Rulers: Plato’s Criticism of Law in the Politicus.” British Journal of the History of Philosophy 28(6): 10531070.Google Scholar
Dybikowski, J. 1970. “False Pleasure and the Philebus.Phronesis 15: 147165.Google Scholar
Eklund, M. 2017. Choosing Normative Concepts. Oxford.Google Scholar
El Murr, D. 2019. “Pourquoi le Bien? Apparence, realité et le désir du Bien (République VI, 504B–506D).” Journal of Ancient Philosophy, supplementary vol. I: 2641.Google Scholar
Enders, M. 1999. “Platons Theologie: Der Gott, die Götter, und das Gute.” Perspektiven der Philosophie, Neues Jahrbuch 25: 131185.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism. Oxford.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2021. “Thanks, We’re Good: Why Moral Realism Is Not Morally Objectionable.Philosophical Studies 178: 16891699.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erler, M. 2007. Die Philosophie der Antike. Vol. II, Platon. Basel.Google Scholar
Evans, M. 2010. “A Partisan Guide to Socratic Intellectualism.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives, edited by Tenenbaum, S.. Oxford: 625.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. 1947. The Definition of Good. London.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. 1973. Value and Reality. London.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. 1989. Platons Idee des Guten. 2nd ed. Sankt Augustin.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. 2002. “The Absolute Good and the Human Goods.” In New Images of Plato: Dialogues on the Good, edited by Reale, G. and Scolnicov, S.. Sankt Augustin: 187196.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. 2020 [1991]. “Sokrates: Tugend ist Wissen.” In Platonische Aufsätze. Berlin/Boston: 828.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. 2020 [2013]. “Was jede Seele sucht und worumwillen sie alles tut.” In Platonischen Aufsätze. Berlin/Boston: 93113.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. and Damschen, G. 2015. “Is the Idea of the Good Beyond Being? Plato’s epekeina tês ousias Revisited (Republic 6, 509b8–10).” In Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, edited by Nails, D. and Tarrant, H.. Helsinki: 197203.Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. 2001. “La causalità del Bene nella ‘Repubblia’ di Platone.” Elenchos 1: 537.Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. 2003. “L’idea del bene: collocazione ontologicaa e funzione causale.” In La Repubblica: Traduzione e commento, Vol V, edited by Vegetti, M.. Naples: 287325.Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. 2020. “Il Bene e il demiurgo: identità o gerarchia? Il conflitto delle interpretazioni nel medioplatonismo.” In Interpretare Platone, edited by Gatti, M. and De Simone, P.. Milan: 239261.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. R. F. 1992. “Platonic Love.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by Kraut, R.. Cambridge, UK: 248276.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (ed.). 2011. The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 2001. Natural Goodness. Oxford.Google Scholar
Forest, P. 1996. God without the Supernatural. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1969. “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.” Journal of Philosophy 66: 829839.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1971. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy 68: 520.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1992. “Introduction.” Plato: Protagoras, translated with notes by S. Lombardo and K. Bell. Indianapolis, IN: viixxxiii.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1996. “Introduction.” In Rationality in Greek Thought, edited by Frede, M. and Striker, G.. Oxford: 128.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 2017. “The Science of Measuring Pleasure and Pain.” In Plato’s Protagoras: Essays on the Confrontation of Philosophy and Sophistry, edited by Pettersson, O. and Songe-Møller, V.. Dordrecht: 123136.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.G. 1986. The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy, translated by P. C. Smith. New Haven, CT.Google Scholar
Gaiser, K. 1963. Platons ungeschriebene Lehre: Studien zur systematischen und geschichtlichen Begründung der Wissenschaften in der Platonischen Schule. Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Gaita, R. 2004. Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception. 2nd ed. London.Google Scholar
Ganson, T. 2009. “The Rational/Non-Rational Distinction in Plato’s Republic.Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36: 179197.Google Scholar
Gauthier, R. A. and Jolif, J. Y 1970 [1958–1959]. L’Ethique à Nicomaque, 2nd ed. 2 vols. Paris.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 1997. “Socrates’ Absolutist Prohibition of Wrongdoing.” In Wisdom, Ignorance, and Virtue: New Essays in Socratic Studies, edited by McPherran, M.. Edmonton, AL: 111.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2003. Knowing Persons: A Study in Plato. Oxford.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2006. “A Platonic Reading of Plato’s Symposium.” In Plato’s Symposium: Issues in Interpretation and Reception, edited by Lesher, J., Nails, D., and Sheffield, F.. Cambridge, MA: 4767.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2013. From Plato to Platonism. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2014a. “The Myth of Plato’s Socratic Period.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96: 403430.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2014b. “Plato’s Rational Souls.” Review of Metaphysics 67: 3759.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2015. “Ideas of Good?” In Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, edited by Nails, D. and Tarrant, H.. Helsinki: 225242.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2018. “Socrates’ Autobiography: An Epitome of Platonism.” In Plato’s Phaedo: Selected Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum, edited by Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F.. Baden-Baden: 323327.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2019. “Virtue with and without Philosophy in Plato and Plotinus.” In Passionate Mind: Essays in Honor of John Rist, edited by David, B.. Sankt Augustin: 191208.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2020. Platonism and Naturalism: The Possibility of Philosophy. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2000. “The Body’s Fault? Plato’s Timaeus on Psychic Illness.” In Reason and Necessity: Essays on Plato’s Timaeus, edited by Wright, R.. London: 5984.Google Scholar
Gersh, S. 1973. ΚΙΝΗΣΙΣ ΑΚΙΝΗΤΟΣ: A Study in Spiritual Motion. Leiden.Google Scholar
Goetz, S. 2005. “Frankfurt-Style Counterexamples and Begging the Question.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29: 83105.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. 1973. Plato: The Arguments of the Philosophers. London.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. 1975. Plato: Philebus. Oxford.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. 1978. “Plato’s Moral Theory.” Philosophical Books 19(3): 97102.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. and Taylor, C. C. W. 1982. The Greeks on Pleasure. Oxford.Google Scholar
Gould, J. 1955. The Development of Plato’s Ethics. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Griswold, C. 1986. Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus. New Haven, CT.Google Scholar
Grube, G. M. A. 1935. Plato’s Thought. London.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1975. A History of Greek Philosophy: IV. Plato: The Man and His Dialogues. Earlier Period. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1978. A History of Greek Philosophy: V. The Later Plato and the Academy. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Hacker-Wright, J. 2009. “Human Nature, Virtue, and Rationality.” Philosophy 84: 413427.Google Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1946. “Moral Evil and Ignorance in Plato’s Ethics.” The Classical Quarterly 40(3/4): 118120.Google Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1965 [1936]. “Plato’s Theism.” In Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, edited by Allen, R. E.. London: 439447.Google Scholar
Hager, F. P. 1962. “Die Materie und das Böse im antiken Platonismus.” Museum Helveticum 19(2): 73103Google Scholar
Hager, F. P. 1970. Die Vernunft und das Problem des Bösen im Rahmen der platonischen Ethik und Metaphysik. Bern.Google Scholar
Hager, F. P. 1987. Gott und das Böse im antiken Platonismus. Würzburg.Google Scholar
Halfwassen, J. 1997. “Monismus und Dualismus in Platons Prinzipienlehre.Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch für Antike und Mittelalter 2: 121.Google Scholar
Halfwassen, J. 2015. Auf den Spuren des Einen. Tübingen.Google Scholar
Hall, R. W. 1963. Plato and the Individual. The Hague.Google Scholar
Hampton, C. 1987. “Pleasure, Truth, and Being in Plato’s Philebus: A Reply to Professor Frede.” Phronesis 32: 253262.Google Scholar
Hampton, C. 1990. Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being: An Analysis of Plato’s Philebus. Albany, NY.Google Scholar
Hanann, N. 2020. “Knowledge and Voluntary Injustice in the Hippias Minor.” Apeiron. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2020-0031: 125.Google Scholar
Happ, H. 1971. Hyle: Studien zum aristotelischen Materie-Begriff. Berlin.Google Scholar
Haraldsen, V. 2017. “Is Pleasure Any Good? Weakness of Will and the Art of Measurement in Plato’s Protagoras.” In Plato’s Protagoras: Essays on the Confrontation of Philosophy and Sophistry, edited by Pettersson, O. and Songe-Møller, V.. Dordrecht: 99121.Google Scholar
Hardy, J. 2014. “Is Virtue Knowledge? Socratic Intellectualism Reconsidered.” In Ancient Ethics, edited by Hardy, J. and Rudebusch, G.. Göttingen: 141170.Google Scholar
Hardy, J. and Rudebusch, G. (eds.). 2014. Ancient Ethics. Göttingen.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1977. The Nature of Morality. Oxford.Google Scholar
Harman, G. and Thompson, J. 1996. Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity. Oxford.Google Scholar
Harte, V. 2004. “The Philebus on Pleasure: The Good, the Bad, and the False.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104: 113130.Google Scholar
Hayward, M. 2019. “Immoral Realism.” Philosophical Studies 176: 897914.Google Scholar
Herrmann, F.-G. 2007. “The Idea of the Good and the Other Forms in Plato’s Republic.” In Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, D., Hermann, F. G., and Penner, T.. Edinburgh: 202230.Google Scholar
Herzberg, S. 2017. “Aristoteles Metaphysik des Guten.” Theologie und Philosophie 92: 532559.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, D. 1982. “The Good in Plato’s Republic.” Apeiron 19(2): 6592.Google Scholar
Höffe, O. 1996. Praktische Philosophie – Das Modell des Aristoteles. 2nd ed. Berlin.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, M. 1996. Die Entstehung von Ordnung: Zur Bestimmung von Sein, Erkennen und Handeln in der späteren Philosophie Platons. Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Horn, C. 1998. Antike Lebenskunst: Glück und Moral von Sokrates bis zu den Neuplatonikern. Munich.Google Scholar
Horn, C. 2016. “The Unity of the World-Order According to Metaphysics Λ 10.” In Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda – New Essays, edited by Horn, C.. Boston: 269293.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. 2013. “An Ontological Proof of Moral Realism.” Social Philosophy and Policy 30(1–2): 259279.Google Scholar
Huffman, C. 2005. Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher, and Mathematical King. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 1987. “‘Good’ and ‘Good For.’” Mind 86: 7173.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2020. “Against ‘Good For’/‘Well-Being’, For ‘Simply Good.’” Philosophical Quarterly 71(4): 803822.Google Scholar
Ilievski, V. 2014. Platonic Theodicy and the Platonic Cause of Evil (Ph.D. dissertation, Central European University).Google Scholar
Ilievski, V. 2016. “Plato’s Theodicy in the Timaeus.” Rhizomata 4(2): 201224.Google Scholar
Irani, T. 2021. “Socrates’s Great Speech: The Defense of Philosophy in Plato’s Gorgias.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 59(3): 349369.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977. Plato’s Moral Theory. Oxford.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1992 [1986]. “Socrates the Epicurean?” In Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates, edited by Benson, H.. Oxford: 198219.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 2007. The Development of Ethics, Vol. I. Oxford.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1943 [1936]. Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture. 3 vols. Translated by G. Highet. New York.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2020. “From Craft to Nature: The Emergence of Natural Teleology.” In The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Science, edited by Taub, L.. Cambridge, UK: 102120.Google Scholar
Jonas, M. 2018. “The Role of Practice and Habituation in Socrates’ Theory of Ethical Development.” British Journal of the History of Philosophy 26(6): 9871005.Google Scholar
Jones, R. 2012. “Rational and Nonrational Desires in Meno and Protagoras.” Analytic Philosophy 53: 224233.Google Scholar
Jordan, J. 2019. “Natural Normativity and the Authority-of-Nature Challenge.” International Philosophical Quarterly 59(1): 2336.Google Scholar
Jordan, M. 2013. “Theism, Naturalism, and Meta-Ethics.” Philosophy Compass 8: 373380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jorgenson, C. 2016. “Becoming Immortal in the Symposium and the Timaeus.” In Plato in Symposium: Selected Papers from the Tenth Symposium Platonicum, edited by Tulli, M. and M.Erler, . Sankt Augustin: 243248.Google Scholar
Jorgenson, C. 2018. The Embodied Soul in Plato’s Later Thought. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Jorgenson, C. 2021. “Responsibility, Causality, and Will in the Timaeus.” In Plato’s Timaeus: Proceedings of the 10th Symposium Platonicum Pragense, edited by Jorgenson, C., Karfik, F., and Ŝpinka, F.. Leiden and Boston: 259273.Google Scholar
Joyce, R. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Joyce, R. 2006. The Evolution of Morality. Boston, MA.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. 1992 [1981]. “Did Plato Write Socratic Dialogues?” In Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates, edited by Benson, H. Oxford: 3552.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. 1987. “Plato’s Theory of Desire.” Review of Metaphysics 41: 77103.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. 2002. “On Platonic Chronology.” In New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and Ancient, edited by Annas, J. and Rowe, C.. Cambridge, MA: 93127.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 1998. “Imperfect Virtue.” Ancient Philosophy 18: 315339.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2006. “Plato on the Attribution of Cognitive Attitudes.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88: 127162.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2017a. Plato’s Moral Psychology. Oxford.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2017b. “Plato’s Ethical Psychology.” In The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics, edited by Bobonich, C.. Cambridge, UK: 7285.Google Scholar
Kane, R. 2019. “Dimensions of Responsibility: Freedom of Action and Freedom of Will.” Social Philosophy and Policy 36(1): 114131.Google Scholar
Karamanolis, G. 2004. “Transformations of Plato’s Ethics: Platonist Interpretations of Plato’s Ethics from Antiochus to Porphyry.Rhizai 1: 73105.Google Scholar
Karfik, F. 2004. Die Beseelung des Kosmos: Untersuchungen zur Kosmologie, Seelenlehre und Theologie in Platons Phaidon und Timaios. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Katsimanis, K. S. 1977. Étude sur le rapport entre le beau et le bien chez Platon. Lille.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. 2019. “Rationality as the Rule of Reason.” Nous 53: 122.Google Scholar
Kolodny, N. 2005. “Why Be Rational?Mind 114: 509563.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1983. “Two Distinctions in Goodness.” Philosophical Review 92, 2: 169195.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2018. “Prospects for a Naturalistic Explanation of the Good.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary vol. 92: 111131.Google Scholar
Kosman, L. A. 1976. “Platonic Love.” In Facets of Plato’s Philosophy, edited by Werkmeister, W. H.. Assen: 5369.Google Scholar
Kosman, L. A. 2007. “Justice and Virtue: The Republic’s Inquiry into Proper Difference.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, edited by Ferrari, G. R. F.. Cambridge, UK: 116137.Google Scholar
Krämer, H. J. 1959. Arete bei Platon und Aristoteles. Heidelberg.Google Scholar
Krämer, H. J. 1967 [1964]. Der Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik: Untersuchungen zur Geschichte des Platonismus zwischen Platon und Plotin. Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Krämer, H. J. 2014 [1969]. “Nochmals: Für die Frühdatierung des platonischen Vortrags ‘Über das Gute’ bei Aristoxenus.” In Gesammelte Aufsätze zu Platon, edited by Mirbach, D.. Berlin: 241270.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (ed.) 1992. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2011. Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford.Google Scholar
Kronqvist, C. 2019. “A Personal Love of the Good.” Philosophia 47: 977994.Google Scholar
Krüger, G. 1948. Einsicht und Leidenschaft: Das Wesen des platonischen Denkens. Frankfurt.Google Scholar
Lafrance, Y. 1995. “Métrétique, mathématiques et dialectique en Politique 283 C-285 C.” In Reading the Statesman: Proceedings of the III Symposium Platonicum, edited by Rowe, C.. Sankt Augustin: 89101.Google Scholar
Laks, A. 1990. “Legislation and Demiurgy: On the Relationship Between Plato’s Republic and Laws.” Classical Antiquity 9(2): 209229.Google Scholar
Lane, M. 1998. Method and Politics in Plato’s Statesman. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Lang, P. M. 2010. “The Ranking of Goods at Philebus 66A–67B.” Phronesis 55: 153169.Google Scholar
Lavecchia, S. 2006. Una via che conduce al divino: La “homoiosis theo” nella filosofia di Platone. Milan.Google Scholar
Lavecchia, S. 2010. Oltre l’uno ed i molti: Bene ed essere nella filosofia di Platone. Milan.Google Scholar
Layne, D. 2019. “Double Ignorance and the Perversion of Self-Knowledge.” In Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy, edited by Ambury, J. and German, A.. Cambridge, UK: 206222.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 1983. “Ethics, Mathematics, and Relativism.” Mind 92(365): 3860.Google Scholar
Ledger, G. R. 1989. Re-counting Plato: A Computer Analysis of Plato’s Style. Oxford.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2015. “Normativity for Naturalists.” Philosophical Issues 25(1): 6479.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2019. “The Death of God and the Death of Morality.” Monist 102: 386402.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. 1979. Value and Existence. London.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. 2019. “What God Might Be.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85: 6375.Google Scholar
Liske, M. T. 1987. “Ist Platons Ethik deontologisch oder teleologisch?Salzburger Jahrbücher für Philosophie 32: 6577.Google Scholar
Lodge, R. 1928. Plato’s Theory of Ethics. London.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. 2021. “Politics and Divinity in Plato’s Republic: The Form of the Good.” In Themes in Plato, Aristotle and Hellenistic Philosophy, edited by Leigh, F.. London: 6382.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.Google Scholar
Lott, M. 2014. “Why Be a Good Human Being? Natural Goodness, Reason, and the Authority of Human Nature.” Philosophia 42: 761777.Google Scholar
Louden, R. 1996. “Towards a Genealogy of ‘Deontology.’” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34: 571592.Google Scholar
Mabbott, J. D. 1971. “Is Plato’s Republic Utilitarian?” In Plato. Ethics, Politics, and Philosophy of Art and Religion, edited by Vlastos, G.. Garden City, NJ: 5765.Google Scholar
MacDonald, S. (ed.). 1991. Being and Goodness: The Concept of Good in Metaphysical and Philosophical Theology. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, M. M. 1981. Plato on Punishment. Berkeley, CA.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism. Oxford.Google Scholar
Männlein-Robert, I. 2013. “Tugend, Flucht und Ekstase: zur ὁμοίωσις θεῷ in Kaiserzeit und Spätantike.” In Pietsch, C. (ed.), Ethik des antiken Platonismus: der platonische Weg zum Glück in Systematik Entstehung und historischem Kontext. Stuttgart: 99111.Google Scholar
Márquez, X. 2012. A Stranger’s Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy, and Law in Plato’s Statesman. Las Vegas.Google Scholar
Marshall, C. 2018. Compassionate Moral Realism. Oxford.Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M. 2005. “Out of the Labyrinth: Plato’s Attack on Consequentialism.” In Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, edited by Gill, C.. Oxford: 191214.Google Scholar
McGinley, J. 1977. “The Doctrine of Good in Philebus.” Apeiron 11: 2757.Google Scholar
McTighe, K. 1983. “Nine Notes on Plato’s Lysis.” American Journal of Philology 104(1): 6782.Google Scholar
McTighe, K. 1984. “Socrates on Desire for the Good and the Unwillingness of Wrongdoing: Gorgias 466A–468E.” Phronesis 29: 193236.Google Scholar
Meldrum, M. 1950. “Plato on the ἀρχὴ κακῶν.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 70: 6574.Google Scholar
Mele, A. 1987. Irrationality. Oxford.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 1992. “Aristotle and Plato on God as Nous and as the Good.” Review of Metaphysics 45(3): 543573.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 1995. Plato on God as Nous. Carbondale, IL.Google Scholar
Merker, A. 2011. Une Morale pour les mortels: L’éthique de Platon et Aristote. Paris.Google Scholar
Merlan, P. 1953. From Platonism to Neoplatonism. The Hague.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. 2014. “God Is Not to Blame: Divine Creation and Human Responsibility in Plato’s Timaeus.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 29: 5569.Google Scholar
Migliori, M. and Napolitano, L. (eds.) 2003. Plato Ethicus: Philosophy Is Life. Sankt Augustin.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 1985. “Platonic Provocations: Reflections on the Soul and the Good in the Republic.” In Platonic Investigations, edited by O’Meara, D.. Washington, DC: 163193.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 1990. “The God-Given Way.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 6: 323359.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 2004 [1980]. The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman with “Dialectical Education and Unwritten Teachings in Plato’s Statesman”. Las Vegas.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 2007. “Beginning the ‘Longer Way.’” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, edited by Ferrari, G. R. F.. Cambridge, UK: 310344.Google Scholar
Mirus, C. 2012. “Order and the Determinate: Good as a Metaphysical Concept in Aristotle.” The Review of Metaphysics 65(3): 499523.Google Scholar
Mitsis, P. 1988. Epicurus’ Ethical Theory: The Pleasures of Invulnerability. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Mohr, R. 1989. “Plato’s Theology Reconsidered: What the Demiurge Does.” In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, Vol. III, Plato, edited by Anton, J. and Preus, A.. Albany, NY: 293307.Google Scholar
Monteils-Laeng, L. 2014. Agir sans vouloir. Paris.Google Scholar
Moore, C. 2015. Socrates and Self-Knowledge. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1971 [1903]. Principia Ethica. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Moran, R. 2001. Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Morris, M. 2006. “Akrasia in the Protagoras and the Republic.” Phronesis 51: 195229.Google Scholar
Morrow, G. 1960. Plato’s Cretan City. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Morton, J. 2019. “Can Theists Avoid Epistemological Objections to Moral (and Normative) Realism.” Faith and Philosophy 36(3): 291312.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2008. “Appearances and Calculations: Plato’s Division of the Soul.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34: 3568.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2012. Aristotle on the Apparent Good. Oxford.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2014. “Hedonism and the Divided Soul in Plato’s Protagoras.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96: 285319.Google Scholar
Mulgan, T. 2015. Purpose in the Universe. Oxford.Google Scholar
Murdoch, I. 1970. The Sovereignty of Good. London.Google Scholar
Murdoch, I. 1977. The Fire and the Sun. Oxford.Google Scholar
Murdoch, I. 1992. Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals. London.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1986. The View From Nowhere. Oxford.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 2005. “The Problem of Global Justice.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33(2): 113147.Google Scholar
Nehemas, A. 1999. “Socratic Intellectualism.” In Virtues of Authenticity. Princeton: 27–58. (Reprinted from Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 2, edited by J. Cleary. Langham, MD, 1987: 275–316.)Google Scholar
Nettleship, R. L. 1961 [1897]. Lectures on the Republic of Plato. London. (Reprinted in 1901 as “Plato’s Conception of Goodness and the Good.” In Philosophical Remains, edited by Bradley, A. C., 2nd ed. London: 237398.)Google Scholar
Nightingale, A. 1996. “Plato on the Origins of Evil: The Statesman Myth Reconsidered.” Ancient Philosophy 16: 6591.Google Scholar
Nill, M. 1985. Morality and Self-Interest in Protagoras, Antiphon, and Democritus. Leiden.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. 2003. “Socrates and Protagoras on Virtue.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 24: 59131.Google Scholar
O’Brien, M. 1958. “Modern Philosophy and Platonic Ethics.” Journal of the History of Ideas 19: 451472.Google Scholar
O’Brien, M. 1967. The Socratic Paradoxes and the Greek Mind. Chapel Hill, NC.Google Scholar
Oddie, G. 2005. Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford.Google Scholar
Orsi, F. 2015. “The Guise of the Good.” Philosophy Compass 10: 714724.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2006. “Normativity.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1: 325380.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters. Volumes 1 and 2. Oxford.Google Scholar
Pasnau, R. 2021. “Where Socratic Akrasia Meets the Platonic Good.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 59(1): 121.Google Scholar
Patzig, G. 1971. Ethik ohne Metaphysik. Göttingen.Google Scholar
Pears, D. 1984. Motivated Irrationality. Oxford.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1971. “Thought and Desire in Plato.” In Plato II, edited by Vlastos, G.. New York: 96118.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1973a. “Socrates on Virtue and Motivation.” In Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, edited by Lee, E., Mourelatos, A., and Rorty, R.. Phronesis supplementary Vol. 1: 133151.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1973b. “The Unity of Virtue.” Philosophical Review 82(1): 3568.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1991. “Desire and Power in Socrates: The Argument of Gorgias 466A–468E that Orators and Tyrants have no Power in the City.” Apeiron 24: 147202.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1992. “Socrates and the Early Dialogues.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by Kraut, R.. Cambridge, UK: 121169.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1996. “Knowledge vs. True Belief in the Socratic Psychology of Action.” Apeiron 19: 199230.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1997. “Socrates on the Strength of Knowledge: Protagoras 351B–357E.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79: 117149.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2002. “The Historical Socrates and Plato’s Early Dialogues: Some Philosophical Questions.” In New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and Ancient, edited by Annas, J. and Rowe, C.. Washington, DC: 189212.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2003. “The Forms, the Form of the Good, and the Desire for the Good in Plato’s Republic.” Modern Schoolman 80: 191233.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2005. “Socratic Ethics, Ultra Realism, Determinism, and Ethical Truth.” In Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, edited by Gill, C.. Oxford: 157187.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2007a. “The Good, Advantage, Happiness, and the Form of the Good: How Continuous is Socratic Ethics with Platonic Ethics?” In Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, D, Herrmann, F.-G., and Penner, T, Edinburgh: 93123.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2007b. “What Is the Form of the Good the Form of? A Question About the Plot of the Republic.” In Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, D, Herrmann, F.-G., and Penner, T., Edinburgh: 1541.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2011. “Socratic Ethics and the Socratic Psychology of Action.” In The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, edited by Morrison, D.. New York: 260292.Google Scholar
Penner, T. and Rowe, C. 2005. Plato’s Lysis. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Perl, E. 2014. Thinking Being: Introduction to Metaphysics in the Classical Tradition. Leiden.Google Scholar
Petrucci, F. 2017. “Plato on Virtue in the Menexenus.” Classical Quarterly 67(1): 4970.Google Scholar
Pietsch, C. (ed.) 2013. Ethik des antiken Platonismus: Der platonische Weg zum Glück in Systematik, Entstehung und historischem Kontext. Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Pölzler, T. 2019. “How to Determine Whether Evolution Debunks Moral Realism.” Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft und Ethik 23(1): 3560.Google Scholar
Pradeau, J.-F. 1997. Platon et la cité. Paris.Google Scholar
Pradeau, J.-F. 2002. Plato and the City. Translated by Janet Lloyd. Exeter.Google Scholar
Prauscello, L. 2014. Performing Citizenship in Plato’s Laws. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 1989. Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 1995. Mental Conflict. London and New York.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 1996. “Plato’s Ethics.” Ancient Philosophy 16(1): 189194.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 2009. “Are Plato’s Soul-Parts Psychological Subjects.” Ancient Philosophy 29(1): 115.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. 2011. Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle. New York.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 1968. Moral Obligation and Duty and Interest. Oxford.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 2003 [1928]. Moral Writings, edited by MacAdams, J.. Oxford.Google Scholar
Primavesi, O. 2012. “Aristotle’s Metaphysics A: A New Critical Edition with Introduction.” In C. Steel, Aristotle’s Metaphysics Alpha, edited by Steel, C.. Oxford: 385516.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 2005. Ethics without Ontology. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 2015. “Naturalism, Realism, and Normativity.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1(2): 312328.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 1995. “Moral Realism.” The Philosophical Review 95: 163207.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2003. Facts, Values, and Norms: Towards a Morality of Consequence. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Rawson, G. 1996. “Knowledge and Desire for the Good in Plato’s Republic.” Southwest Philosophy Review 12(1): 103115.Google Scholar
Rea, M. 2006. “Naturalism and Moral Realism.” In Knowledge and Reality, edited by Davidson, M.. Crisp, T., and Vander Laan, D.. Dordrecht: 215242.Google Scholar
Reale, G. 1997 [1984]. Toward a New Interpretation of Plato. Translated by J. Catan. Washington, DC. (10th edition 1991, Per una nuova interpretazione di Platone: Rilettura della metafisica dei grandi dialoghi alla luce “Doctrine non scritte.”)Google Scholar
Reale, G. 2003. “‘Henological’ Basis of Plato’s Ethics.” In Plato Ethicus: Philosophy Is Life. Proceedings of the International Colloquium Piacenza, edited by Migliori, M. and Napolitano, L.. Sankt Augustin: 255264.Google Scholar
Reed, D. 2020. “Deficient Virtue in the Phaedo.” Classical Quarterly 70(1): 119130.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 1988. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato’s Republic. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 1989. Socrates in the Apology. Indianapolis, IN.Google Scholar
Renaud, F. 1999. Die Resokratisierung Platons: Die platonische Hermeneutik Hans-Georg Gadamers. Sankt Augustin.Google Scholar
Renaut, O. 2019. “The Analogy Between Vice and Disease from the Republic and the Timaeus.” In Psychology and Ontology in Plato, edited by Pitteloud, L. and Keeling, E.. Cham: 6783.Google Scholar
Renz, U. 2017. “Self-Knowledge as a Personal Achievement.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 117(3): 253272.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. 2010. Axiogenesis: An Essay in Metaphysical Optimalism. Lanham, MD.Google Scholar
Rice, H. 2000. God and Goodness. Oxford.Google Scholar
Richard, M.-D. 2005. L’enseignement oral de Platon. Paris.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 1998. “The Possibility of Morality in Plato’s Republic.” Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 14: 5372.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 2002. Real Ethics: Rethinking the Foundations of Morality. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 2012. Plato’s Moral Realism. Washington, DC.Google Scholar
Ritter, C. 1933. The Essence of Plato’s Philosophy. Translated by A. Alles. London.Google Scholar
Roberts, J. 1987. “Plato on the Causes of Wrongdoing in the Laws.” Ancient Philosophy 7: 2337.Google Scholar
Robin, L. 1908. La theorie platonicienne de l’amour. Paris.Google Scholar
Rodier, G. 1957 [1924]. Études de philosophie grecque. Paris.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1939. The Foundations of Ethics. Oxford.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1951. Plato’s Theory of Ideas. Oxford.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. 1976. An Introduction to Greek Ethics. London.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. 2005. “What Difference Do Forms Make to Platonic Epistemology.” In Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, edited by Gill, C.. Oxford: 215232.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. 2007. “The Form of the Good and the Good in Plato’s Republic.” In Pursuing the Good. Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, D., Hermann, F. G., and Penner, T.. Edinburgh: 124153.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. and Schofield, M. (eds.). 2000. The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political Thought. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Rowett, C. 2016. “Why the Philosopher Kings Will Believe the Noble Lie.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 50: 67100.Google Scholar
Rowlands, M. 2018. “Self-Awareness and Korsgaard’s Naturalistic Explanation of the Good.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary Vol. 92: 133149.Google Scholar
Rudebusch, G. 2003. “Socratic Perfectionism.” In Plato and Socrates: Desire, Identity, and Existence, edited by Reshotko, N.. Edmonton: 127141.Google Scholar
Rudebusch, G. 2007. “Socratic Neutralism.” In The Good and the Form of the Good, edited by Cairns, D., Herrmann, F.-G., and Penner, T.. Edinburgh: 7692.Google Scholar
Rudebusch, G. 2017. “The Unity of Virtue, Ambiguity, and Socrates’ Higher Purpose.” Apeiron 37: 1014.Google Scholar
Rudebusch, G. 2020. “Philebus 11B: Good or the Good.” Apeiron 53(2): 161185.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. 1989. The Darwinian Paradigm. London.Google Scholar
Russell, D. 2005. Plato on Pleasure and the Good Life. Oxford.Google Scholar
Sachs, D. 1963. “A Fallacy in Plato’s Republic.” Philosophical Review 72: 141158.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 1966. “Plato’s Protagoras and Explanations of Weakness.” Philosophical Review 75: 333.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 1979. Socrates: Philosophy in Plato’s Early Dialogues. London.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 1985. “Two Theories of Good in Plato’s Republic.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 67: 223245.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 2002. “The Form of the Good as Paradigm and Its Essence.” In New Images of Plato, edited by Reale, G. and Scolnicov, S.. Sankt Augustin: 359378.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 2010. Understanding Plato’s Republic. Malden, MA.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. 1989. “Existentialism Is a Humanism.” In Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre, edited by Kaufmann, W.. New York.Google Scholar
Sassi, M. 2008. “The Self, the Soul, and the Individual in the City of the Laws.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 35: 127148.Google Scholar
Saunders, T. 1968. “The Socratic Paradoxes in Plato’s Laws. A Commentary on 859 C-864B.” Hermes 96: 421434.Google Scholar
Saunders, T. 1991. Plato’s Penal Code. Oxford.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. 1995. Plato’s Literary Garden: How to Read a Platonic Dialogue. Notre Dame, IN.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. 2006. Metaphysics and Method in Plato’s Statesman. Cambridge.Google Scholar
Sayre-McCord, G. 1988. “The Many Moral Realisms.” In Essays on Moral Realism, edited by Sayre-McCord, G.. Ithaca, NY: 126.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2006. Plato: Political Philosophy. Oxford.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2011. “Plato in His Time and Place.” In The Oxford Handbook of Plato, edited by Fine, G.. Oxford: 3662.Google Scholar
Schöpsdau, K. 1984. “Zum Strafrechtsexkurs in Platons Nomoi.” Rheinisches Museum fϋr Philologie 127(2): 97132.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2007. “Erōs, Philosophy, and Tyranny.” In Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat, edited by Scott, D.. Oxford: 136153.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2015. Levels of Argument: A Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2020. Listening to Reason in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2000. “The Ideal of Godlikeness.” In Plato, edited by Fine, G.. Oxford: 791810.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2007. “Philosophy, the Forms, and the Art of Ruling.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, edited by Ferrari, G. R. F.. Cambridge: 256283.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2009. “Three Kinds of Platonic Immortality.” In Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy, edited by Frede, D. and Reis, B.. Berlin: 145161.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2013. “Socratic Intellectualism in the Republic’s Central Digression.” In The Platonic Art of Philosophy, edited by Boys-Stones, G., El Murr, D., and Gill, C.. Cambridge, UK: 7089.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2014. The Midwife of Platonism. Oxford.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2019. “The Timaeus as Vehicle for Platonic Doctrine.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 56: 4571.Google Scholar
Šegvić, H. 2000. “No One Errs Willingly: The Meaning of Socratic Intellectualism.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 19: 145.Google Scholar
Seifert, J. 2002. “The Idea of the Good as the Sum-Total of Pure Perfections.” In New Images of Plato: Dialogues on the Idea of the Good, edited by Reale, G. and Scolnicov, S.. Sankt Augustin: 407424.Google Scholar
Senn, S. J. 2005. “Virtue as the Sole Intrinsic Good in Plato’s Early Dialogues.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 28: 121.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defense. Oxford.Google Scholar
Sheffield, F. 2017. “Plato on Love and Friendship.” In The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics, edited by Bobonich, C.. Cambridge, UK: 86102.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2007. “Unified Agency and Akrasia in Plato’s Republic.” In Akrasia in Greek Philosophy, edited by Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P.. Leiden: 6186.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2015. “The summum bonum in Aristotle’s Ethics: Fractured Goodness.” In The Highest Good in Aristotle and Kant, edited by Aufderheide, J. and Bader, R.. Oxford: 83111.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1888. “Recent Platonism in England.” American Journal of Philology 9(3): 274309.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1895. “The Idea of Good in Plato’s Republic.” University of Chicago Studies in Classical Philology 2: 188239.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1903. The Unity of Plato’s Thought. Chicago.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1908. “A Note on Philebus B, C.” Classical Quarterly 3(3): 343345.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1933. What Plato Said. Chicago.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1902 [1886]. Outline of the History of Ethics. London.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1907 [1874]. The Methods of Ethics. 7th ed. London.Google Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. 2006a. “Reasoning with the Irrational: Moral Psychology in the Protagoras.” Ancient Philosophy 26(1): 244258.Google Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. 2006b. “Plato’s Defense of Justice.” In The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic, edited by Santas, G.. Malden, MA: 263282.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 2004. “Moral Realism.” In Ethics and the A Priori. Cambridge, UK: 181207.Google Scholar
Smith, N. 2004. “Did Plato Write Alcibiades I?Apeiron 37: 93108.Google Scholar
Smith, N. 2014. “Socratic Metaphysics?Apeiron 47(4): 419434.Google Scholar
Smith, N. 2018. “A Problem in Plato’s Hagiography of Socrates.” Athens Journal of Humanities and Arts 5(1): 81103.Google Scholar
Sobel, D. 2016. From Valuing to Value: Towards a Defense of Subjectivism. Oxford.Google Scholar
Solmsen, F. 1942. Plato’s Theology. Ithaca.Google Scholar
Sprigge, T. L. S. 1988. The Rational Foundation of Ethics. London.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F. 1982. “Mental Health and Individual Responsibility in Plato’s Republic.” The Journal of Value Inquiry 15(2): 109124.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F. 1996. “Punishment and the Physiology of the Timaeus.” Classical Quarterly 46(2): 357370.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F. 2000. “Sōphrosunē in the Charmides.” In Plato: Euthydemus, Lysis, Charmides. Proceedings of the V Symposium Platonicum, edited by Robinson, T. M. and Brisson, L.. Sankt Augustin: 265277.Google Scholar
Steel, C. 2012. “Plato as Seen by Aristotle (Metaphysics A 6).” In Aristotle’s Metaphysics Alpha, edited by Steel., C. Oxford: 167200.Google Scholar
Stemmer, P. 1988. “Der Grundriss der platonischen Ethik.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 42: 529569.Google Scholar
Stocker, M. 1979. “Desiring the Bad: An Essay in Moral Psychology.” The Journal of Philosophy 76: 738753.Google Scholar
Storey, D. 2014. “Appearance, Perception, and Non-Rational Belief: Republic 602 C-603A.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 81118.Google Scholar
Street, S. 2008. “Reply to Copp: Naturalism, Normativity, and the Varieties of Realism Worth Worrying About.” Philosophical Issues 18: 207228.Google Scholar
Sturgeon, N. 1988. “Moral Explanations.” In Essays on Moral Realism, edited by Sayre-McCord, G.. Ithaca, NY: 229255.Google Scholar
Sturgeon, N. 2006. “Moral Explanations Defended.” In Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory, edited by Dreiser, J.. London: 241255.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. 1985. Platon und die Schriftlichkeit der Philosophie. Berlin.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. 1997. “Über die Art und Weise der Erörterung der Prinzipien im Timaios.” In Interpreting the Timaeus-Critias, edited by Calvo, T. and Brisson, L.. Sankt Augustin: 195203.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. 2003. Die Idee des Guten in Platons Politeia. Sankt Augustin.Google Scholar
Taylor, A. E. 1924. Platonism and Its Influence. Boston, MA.Google Scholar
Taylor, A. E. 1928. A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus. Oxford.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W. 1976. Plato’s Protagoras. Translation with notes. Oxford.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W. 1998. “Platonic Ethics.” In Ethics: Companions to Ancient Thought 4, edited by Everson, S.. Cambridge, UK: 4976.Google Scholar
Thalberg, I. 1962. “False Pleasures.” Journal of Philosophy 59(3): 6574.Google Scholar
Thesleff, H. 2009. Platonic Patterns: A Collection of Studies. Las Vegas.Google Scholar
Timmermann, F. 2019. Der Magnetismus des Guten. Berlin.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 2000. “Sull’ Etica di Platone in Margine a un Novo Commento allo ‘Republica.’” Rivista di Storia della Filosofia 55(4): 607618.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 2020. La filosofia di Platone: Verità e ragione umana. Rome.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 2022. “Antiochus of Aascalon’s ‘Platonic’ Ethics.Elenchos 43(1): 85103.Google Scholar
Van Ackeren, M. 2003. Das Wissen vom Guten: Bedeutung und Kontinuität des Tugendwissens in den Dialogen Platons. Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Van Camp, J. and Canart, P. 1956. Le sens du mot θεῖος chez Platon. Leuven.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. 1986. “Ability and Responsibility.” In Moral Responsibility, edited by Fischer, J.M.. Ithaca, NY: 153173.Google Scholar
Van Riel, G. 1999. “Beauté, proportion et verité comme ‘vestibule du bien’ dans le Philèbe.” Revue philosophique de Louvain 97: 253267.Google Scholar
Van Riel, G. 2016. Plato’s Gods. London.Google Scholar
Vasiliou, I. 2008. Aiming at Virtue in Plato. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Vasiliou, I. 2015. “Plato, Forms, and Moral Motivation.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 49: 3770.Google Scholar
Vasiliou, I. 2021. “Psychological Eudaimonism and the Natural Desire for the Good: Comments on Rachana Kamtekar’s Plato’s Moral Psychology.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103: 234239.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M. 2003. “Megiston Mathema: L’idea del ‘buono’ e le sue funzioni.” In La Repubblica: Traduzione e commento, Vol. V, Books VI and VII, edited by Vegetti, M.. Naples: 253286.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 1992. “The Guise of the Good.” Noûs 26: 326.Google Scholar
Verdenius, W. J. 1954. “Platons Gottesbegriff.” In La Notion du divin depuis Homère jusqu’à Platon. Entretien Hardt I. Vandoeuvres-Geneva: 241283.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1969. “Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo.” Philosophical Review 78: 291325.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1971a. “Introduction: The Paradox of Socrates.” In The Philosophy of Socrates, edited by Vlastos, G.. Garden City, NY: 121.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1971b. “Justice and Happiness in the Republic.” In Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays. II: Ethics, Politics, and Philosophy of Art and Religion, edited by Vlastos, G.. Garden City, NY: 6695.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1973 [1972]. Platonic Studies. Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1991. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1994. Socratic Studies. Cambridge, UK.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. 2002. Reasonably Vicious. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Vogt, K. 2017. Desiring the Good. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warren, J. 2017. “Plato.” In Cambridge History of Moral Philosophy, edited by Golob, S. and Timmermann, J.. Cambridge, UK: 2841.Google Scholar
Watson, G. 2003. “The Work of the Will.” In Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality, edited by Stround, S. and Tappolet, C.. Oxford: 172200.Google Scholar
Watson, G. 2004 [1975]. “Free Agency.” In Agency and Answerability: Selected Essays. Oxford: 1332.Google Scholar
Weiss, R. 2007. “Thirst as Desire for Good.” In Akrasia in Greek Philosophy from Socrates to Plotinus, edited by Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P.. Leiden: 87100.Google Scholar
White, D. 2007. Myth, Metaphysics, and Dialectic in Plato’s Statesman. Burlington, VT.Google Scholar
White, N. 1985. “Rational Prudence in Plato’s Gorgias.” In Platonic Investigations, edited by O’Meara, D.. Washington, DC: 139162.Google Scholar
White, N. 2006. “Plato’s Conception of Goodness.” In A Companion to Plato, edited by Benson, H.. Malden, MA: 356372.Google Scholar
White, N. 2013. “Plato’s Ethics.” In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, edited by Crisp, R.. Oxford: 2143.Google Scholar
Widerker, D. 2005. “Blameworthiness, Non-robust Alternatives and the Principle of Alternative Expectations.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29: 292306.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Williams, J. (ed.). 2007. Moore’s Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person. Oxford.Google Scholar
Wilberding, J. 2009. “Plato’s Two Forms of Second-Best Morality.” Philosophical Review 118: 351374.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2012. “Akrasia and Self-Rule in Plato’s Laws.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43: 2353.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2013. “Tripartition and the Causes of Criminal Behavior in Laws IX.” Ancient Philosophy 33(1): 111134.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2021. The Political Soul: Plato on Thumos, Spirited Motivation, and the City. Oxford.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. 1986. “Asymmetrical Freedom.” In Moral Responsibility, edited by Fischer, J. M., Ithaca, NY: 225240.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. 2006. “The Ridiculousness of Being Overcome by Pleasure.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31: 113136.Google Scholar
Wolt, D. 2019. “The Involuntary in the Timaeus and the Eudemian Ethics.” Apeiron 52(3): 245272.Google Scholar
Woodruff, P. 2000. “Socrates and the Irrational.” In Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy, edited by Smith, N. and Woodruff, P.. Oxford: 86106.Google Scholar
Wreen, M. 2018. “What Is Moral Relativism?Philosophy 93: 337354.Google Scholar
Zeyl, D. 1989. “Socrates and Hedonism: Protagoras 351b-358d.” In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, Vol. III, Plato, edited by Anton, J. and Preus, A.. Albany, NY: 525.Google Scholar
Zhao, M. 2020. “Meaning, Moral Realism, and the Importance of Morality.” Philosophical Studies 177: 653666.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Plato's Moral Realism
  • Online publication: 28 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009329934.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Plato's Moral Realism
  • Online publication: 28 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009329934.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Plato's Moral Realism
  • Online publication: 28 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009329934.009
Available formats
×