No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 January 2020
In 1972 Gilbert Ryle published a eulogy to Meinong's theory of objects:
Let us frankly concede that Geganstandstheorie itself is dead, buried and not going to be resurrected. Nobody is going to argue again that, for example, “there are objects concerning which it is the case that there are no such objects.”
Since that time, the firm of Routley, Routley, Chisholm and Parsons has vigoruously defended Meinong's theory. Are they advocates for a dead client?
1 Ryle, Gilbert ‘Intentionality and the nature of thinking,’ Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 27 (1973) 255.Google Scholar
2 Richard Routley and Valerie Routley, ‘Rehabilitating Meinong's Theory of Objects,’ Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 27 (1973) 224-54. Chisholm, Roderick M. ‘Homeless objects,’ Revue lnternationale de Philosophie, 27 (1973) 206-23.Google Scholar Parsons, Terence ‘A prolegomenon to Meinongian semantics,’ Journal of Philosophy, 71 (1974) 561-80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3 Hector-Neri Castañeda, ‘Thinking and the structure of the world,’ Critica, 6 (1972) 43-81.
4 For references and discussion of Scott and Grandy see Lambert, Karel ‘Impossible objects,’ Inquiry, 17 (1974) 303-14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar cf. Leblanc, H. and Thomason, R.H. ‘Completeness theorems for some presupposition-free logics,’ Fundamenta Mathematicae, 52 (1968) 125-63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5 For details write Karel Lambert, Dept. of Philosophy, University of California, Irvine.
6 Quine, Willard Van Orman ‘On What There Is,’ in from a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P. 1953) 1.Google Scholar
7 Alexius Meinong, The Theory of Objects, in R. Chisholm, ed., Realism and the Background of Phenomenology (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press 1960) 82.Google Scholar
8 Ibid.
9 See Findlay, J.N. Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values, (Oxford: Oxford U.P. 1963) Ch. VI.Google Scholar
10 Russell, Bertrand The Principles of Mathematics (London: George, Allen & Unwin 1903) 449.Google Scholar
11 Russell, Bertrand ‘On Denoting,’ in Logic and Knowledge, ed. Marsh, R.C. (London: George, Allen & Unwin 1956) 47.Google Scholar
12 Ibid.
13 Lambert, Karel and Fraassen, Bas C. Van Derivation and Counterexample (Encino, Cal.: Dickenson 1972) 160ff.Google Scholar
14 Russell, ‘On Denoting,’ 45.Google Scholar
15 Ibid.
16 Ibid.
17 Leonard Linsky, Meinong's Theory of Objects, Solomon, R.C. ed., in Phenomenology and Existentialism, (New York: Harper and Row 1972) 192.Google Scholar
18 Where M is a well-formed formula in which x is free and t is a singular term, lambda conversion allows us to replace any part ((ƛxM)t) of a formula by , provided that the bound variables of M are distinct both from x and the free variables of t, and stands for the formula which results by substitution of t for x throughout M. See Alonzo Church, The Calculi of Lambda Conversion (1941; rpt. New York: Kraus Reprint, 1965) 9, 12.
19 ‘On Denoting,’ 45.
20 Bertrand Russell, Review of: Meinong, A. Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psycholgie, Mind, (1905) 530; p. 533.Google Scholar
21 Roderick Chisholm, ‘Meinong,’ Encyclopaedia of Philosophy.
22 Bertrand Russell, Review of: Meinong, A. Uber die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften, Mind, (1907) 439.Google Scholar
23 Russell, ‘On Denoting,’ 45.Google Scholar
24 Routley, ‘Rehabilitating Meinong's Theory of Objects.’
25 Russell, Review, Mind (1907), 439.Google Scholar
26 Meinong, Alexius Uber die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften, in Gesamtausgabe, V. S. Hailer, R. Kindinger, R. and Chisholm, R.M. (eds.) (Graz, Austria: Akademische Druck- u. Verlagsanstalt 1973) 223.Google Scholar
27 See Findlay, Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values, 152-3 and Ch. VI passim.
28 Meinong, über die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie, 223.Google Scholar
29 Ibid., 224.
30 Russell, Review, Mind (1907), 439.Google Scholar
31 Meinong, über Möglichkeit und Wahrscheinlichkeit in Gesamtausgabe v. 6, 266.Google Scholar
32 Findlay, 107.