Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b95js Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-07T19:05:00.180Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Indexicality’s Ambivalent Ground

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2025

Constantine V. Nakassis*
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
*
Contact Constantine V. Nakassis at Department of Anthropology, University of Chicago, 1126 E. 59th St., Chicago, IL 60637 (cnakassi@uchicago.edu).
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Through its theorization and elaboration in the path-breaking work of Michael Silverstein, indexicality has served as a foundational analytic category for linguistic anthropology, both in its ethnographic analyses as well as in its theoretical interventions into key issues in the philosophy of language, linguistics, and sociocultural anthropology. The working out of indexicality’s implications for the study of semiosis—and more particularly, language in culture—has and continues to produce a vital and dynamic theoretical field of scholarly activity. This vitality, I argue, emerges from a foundational ambivalence within the category of indexicality: between, on the one hand, immediacy and presence and, on the other hand, mediation and representation. Productively unresolved, this ambivalence is less a problem than an opportunity and invitation for further ethnographic and analytic refinement of our accounts of (meta)semiosis and social life. A reflexive and deconstructive turn to indexicality’s ambivalent ground, then, is implied and necessitated by the category itself, though this in no way obviates its utility for semiotic and ethnographic theory and analysis; indeed, as I argue, such a turn is critical to indexicality’s ongoing utility to both.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 Semiosis Research Center at Hankuk University of Foreign Studies. All rights reserved.

Michael Silverstein’s essay “Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description” (Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b) provides linguistic anthropology’s most important touchstone on indexicality, a concept that has since been central to the field’s interventions into the philosophy of language, linguistics, and sociocultural anthropology. Synthesizing long-standing genealogies of anthropological, linguistic, and philosophical thought (Boas and his students, the Prague circle, and the American pragmatists, among others; cf. Silverstein Reference Silverstein2004, 650), the thrust of these interventions has been to show how language and culture are inherently context- and event-mediated and mediating phenomena; that is, they are indexical phenomena. The focus on indexicality, and the various and far-reaching implications entailed therein, is the fundamental basis of linguistic anthropological analysis and theory today (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016b).

The term indexicality was coined by the American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) to denote a particular kind of semiotic “ground.” One among his well-known trichotomy of icon, index, and symbol, Peirce characterized indexicality as based on a “real connection” (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.287) or “existential relation” (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.243) between a material, token-representamen and its object, such as causality, co-presence, or contiguity (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.306). Typical examples include smoke and fire, a man’s rolling gait and his (probably) being a sailor, the personal pronoun I and the utterer of the token-sign “I,” and, perhaps most canonically, an index finger and what it points to. An indexical ground is not a function of a conventional rule or habit (what Peirce called a Thirdness, as a symbol is) or of shared qualities (a Firstness, as an icon is), but by the actuality (or Secondness) of the relation between some existents in time and space (or at least, the presumption thereof).Footnote 1 A common way of saying this is that indexical signs are intrinsically related to the context of their occurrence (however capacious that context might be; Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Auer and DiLuzio1992).

While Peirce’s semiotic, and the place of indexicality within it, has been in the continual state of being discovered (and forgotten) by scholars since Peirce’s lifetime, it is from Roman Jakobson, who introduced the term indexicality in the latter phase of his career at Harvard in his classic discussion of the grammatical structure of the Russian verb (Reference Jakobson, Waugh and Halle[1957] 1984; see Silverstein Reference Silverstein1975), that the term entered into linguistic anthropological discourse via the work of his student Michael Silverstein. Silverstein brilliantly generalized Jakobson’s insights, showing not just the full range of indexical relations in linguistic structure but also its articulation to the poetic pragmatics of speech in interactional and cultural contexts of usage (Lee Reference Lee1997).

The importance of Silverstein’s expansion of indexicality has not just been that it brought to light new objects or aspects of the study of language and related communicative modalities; nor that it brought together a number of long-standing objects of study into a unified analytic category, though it has done both things, as I discuss below. Rather, it is that the contemplation of indexicality’s implications for the study of semiosis—and more particularly, language in culture—has generated a vital and dynamically growing host of interrelated analytic concepts (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016b). This vitality, I suggest, emerges from a foundational ambivalence within the category of indexicality, and mutatis mutandis within the field of linguistic anthropology. Productively unresolved, this ambivalence—theorized as a dialectics of indexicality—has aided in the progressive program of linguistic anthropology as a science, though this is not without its ironies.

In order to unpack this ambivalence, I first underscore the critical intervention this analytic has been used to make by linguistic anthropology against idealist and structuralist conceptions of language and culture. From there I show that the ground of indexicality conserves something of what it is used to critique, namely, a representationalist ideology and metaphysics of presence.Footnote 2 I then detail how this internal tension has worked itself out through a proliferation of analytic distinctions and supplemental analytics that both explain and exemplify the dialectical semiotic processes that indexicality ambivalently points up. This is, I argue, as it should be, though a heightened reflexivity to this ambivalence is critical, as it opens new directions for the conceptualization of semiosis (and indexicality) in social and cultural life.

Indexicality and SAE Philosophy of Language

One long-standing and consistent strain in Western thinking about language—what we might dub SAE (Standard Average European) philosophy, to adopt a fashion of speaking from Benjamin Lee Whorf (Reference Whorf and Carroll[1939] 1956, 138)Footnote 3—has framed language as a unique and exemplary semiotic, as manifesting a horizon of aspiration that, ironically—as SAE philosophers have consistently lamented—“natural” language, alas, fails to arrive at: a truly autonomous denotational-referential medium that captures its object in its totality, be that Platonic Form in its beautiful ideality and heavenly reason or reality in all its earthy Aristotelian actuality. Language, in this view, stands apart from what it denotes (be this heaven or earth), and its genius (or sin) is that in that distance it (never quite) realizes the universal and true by representing it. The semiotic property of language that allows this is its propositionality, the symbolic ground of language that functions independently of context, free from the messy Matter weighing down sublime (Logical) Form.

Yet if indexicality is that aspect of semiosis that grounds language back in its context of occurrence, one can see why it has long been treated as a residual problem for SAE philosophy of (SAE) language(s). As Bar-Hillel (Reference Bar-Hillel1954) and Garfinkel and Sacks (Reference Garfinkel, Sacks, McKinney and Tiryakian1970, 347–48) both pointed out, the context-bound nature of semiosis has been an insistent thorn in the side of philosophy since the Greeks, one that logicians and others have continually attempted to eliminate or explain away, if only to always find it returned. (Garfinkel and Sacks compare it, in a psychoanalytically redolent and strange midcentury American metaphor, to a housewife compulsively attempting to clean one piece of floor over and over again, without success. We might suggest the equally Sisyphean, yet less gendered, allegory of whack-a-mole.)

Closer to home, we can point to two avatars of this SAE desire: Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), a contemporary of Peirce who mathematized logic (introducing functional analysis to describe propositional structure) and “discovered” the referent-autonomous, logically modelable realm of linguistic sense (Frege Reference Frege, Geach and Black[1892] 1980); and Ferdinand de Saussure (1857–1913), who, along with Frege, set modern linguistics on its course with his distinction of langue and parole (speech), the latter of which, Saussure (Reference Saussure and Harris[1916] 1986) famously argued, had to be excised from langage (language) before a proper linguistic science (of langue) could be possible. Langue was not langage, even if it was its ideal core, that essential kernel that was unique to it: namely, the synchronic, autonomous “system” of differential entities (signifiers) whose nonrandom and language-specific distribution and paradigmatic and syntagmatic relations formed the formal basis for (Fregean) sense (Lee Reference Lee1997; Nakassis Reference Nakassis2013a). Critical to see is how langue and Fregean sense stand apart from the world they denotationally encode, their significance and meaning not dependent on that world in the first instance. In this view, language in its essence is (or should be) free of indexicality, and if indexicality remains, this is as an inessential residue that can, or should, be hived off.

The intervention of linguistic anthropology, and the work of Michael Silverstein in particular, has been to put indexicality at the center of the study of language, and thus reveal the inherent limits of the idealist, semanticizing conceit that has animated both modern formal linguistics and SAE philosophies of language. On the one hand, this has taken the form of arguments that what has been taken as langue has, at its base, indexical relations of various kinds.Footnote 4 The thrust of this critique is that at the heart of langue is parole,Footnote 5 not as an inessential exteriority but as an animating principle of what Silverstein (Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b), following Mauss and Durkheim, has called the “total linguistic fact.”Footnote 6 On the other hand, the focus on indexicality has clarified aspects of linguistic form/meaning and function/practice that are problematically theorized (or simply ignored) within a more narrowly focused formal linguistics, such as deixis, the poetics of interaction, performativity, and language variation, among other topics.Footnote 7 As these various interventions have shown, the indexical processes that characterize language are not unique to it but are more general features of “culture” (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Segal and Yanagisako2005b; Parmentier Reference Parmentier2016, 15); and moreover, what is unique to language—namely, langue—thus serves as an untenable basis for a model of culture—namely, structuralism (Silverstein Reference Silverstein1975, Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 12).Footnote 8

In short, linguistic anthropology has refused the notion of language as an autonomous “system” (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016b), as purely symbolic, purely defined by modalized reference and predication, and thus as essentially divorced from events of use, social relations, or culture. In this, linguistic anthropology has disavowed the representationalist ideologies carried forth by SAE philosophy in its tendencies to semanticize language and culture. Important to highlight is that this semanticization turns on distinguishing and keeping apart word and world, representation and represented. This cut is as much a semiotic ideology (Keane Reference Keane2003) as it an ontology (in the sense of a theory [-logy] of Being [onto-]), one that, as Whorf and Peirce both noted, is characteristic of both SAE philosophy and folk theories of language. This semiotic ideology, we might further suggest, is animated by a particular metaphysics and desire, which we can characterize through the work of Jacques Derrida (Reference Derrida and Spivak1976): namely, a metaphysics of presence and desire for immediation, be it of thought or thing, word or world.

Indexicality as a non-representationalist (i.e., nonsymbolic) form of mediation has been invoked to refuse this metaphysics and its attendant desires. Yet, as I touched on above and detail below, an ambivalence lingers in the category of indexicality and thus in the interventions made in its name. Indexicality retains something of the larger ideological enclosure of representation and metaphysics of presence that it displaces. Perhaps this is because of indexicality’s very definition. Recall Peirce’s formulation of indexicality as a semiotic relation based on a “real connection” or “existential relation.” Might we detect a tension held taut in this definition and diagrammed by it: a tension between questions of mediation (existential relations, real connections) and immediacy (existential relations, real connections), presence and representation, being and semiosis? What kind of tension is this, and by playing on it what notes might we sound?

The Primal Scene of Indexicality

Consider the primal scene of indexicality, a scene that appears in most every foundational treatment of the topic of indexicality and that constitutes, I would argue, our default conceptualization of indexicality: an arm and index finger extended, pointing at some physically co-present object along with the gaze of the eye, attracting and then directing another’s eye to that object. In most accounts, this primal gesture is accompanied by a linguistic sign: a deictically determined noun phrase like “this hat” (Bühler Reference Bühler and Goodwin[1934] 1990, 103–4), a sentential proposition such as “There is a balloon” or “That chair is yellow” (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.293, 7.635), or simply a word-sentence like “slab” (Wittgenstein Reference Wittgenstein1953, pt. 1, §6, §8) or “Gavagai” (Quine Reference Quine1960, 29ff.; Reference Quine1969, 28ff.; cf. Jakobson Reference Jakobson1953, 21).Footnote 9

This pointing index finger is a familiar ur-gesture,Footnote 10 often figured as the basic communicative form that denotational propositionality either aspires to or completes (as in Aristotelian-inspired treatments of the subject), or as that to which propositionality eternally returns so as to actually refer (as Peirce [Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.357] and Bühler Reference Bühler and Goodwin[1934] 1990, 43 both suggest).Footnote 11 In the telling of this primal scene, indexicality in the form of a pointing finger stands at the outset as ambivalent to language (and, by extension, thought), as external to it and yet as somehow central to what it is or was or should be. This extimacy is often emplotted as an origin myth of one sort or another, be it as an ontogenetic narrative of childhood development (Vygotsky Reference Vygotsky1978, 56; cf. Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 231–34), a phylogenetic narrative about the evolution of human communication (Tomasello Reference Tomasello2008; cf. Levinson Reference Levinson, Horn and Ward2004, 98), or even as an anthropological linguistic myth of first contact (Quine Reference Quine1960, Reference Quine1969; also see Wittgenstein Reference Wittgenstein1953, pt. 1, §§1–8).Footnote 12

Embedded in this primal scene, I suggest, is a nagging worry and desire: the worry of mediation and the desire for more immediate encounter (if only at some origin), an ambivalence that pointing is both a self-evident, unproblematic operation (and thus that indexicality a self-evident, unproblematic semiotic ground) and yet also fundamentally underdetermined, ambiguous, shifty, never quite, and thus deeply mediated. Hence, the problem that Willard Quine (Reference Quine1960, 32; Reference Quine1969, 6; also see Jakobson Reference Jakobson1953, 21) famously drew attention to in his thought experiment of the anthropological “jungle” linguist trying (and failing) to determine the referent of the “heathen” “native’s” utterance of “Gavagai” while pointing to a white rabbit scurrying by: even with such a simple, basic act of ostension, how are we to know that the referent or denotation is (the co-present) “rabbit” and not “undetached rabbit parts” or some other ontological and epistemological peculiarity?

This primal scene of pointing dramatizes the basic ideological form of representation that Martin Heidegger (Reference Heidegger, Young and Haynes[1938] 2002) discusses in his essay “The Age of the World Picture.” As Heidegger suggests, the classic notion of representation entails a making present of an object for a subject (say, a rabbit for a linguist), an object figured as exterior to that subject so that it can be seen, and thus known and named, computed and controlled by him (Derrida Reference Derrida, Kamuf, Rottenberg, Caws and Caws[1980] 2002). Here representation operates within a historically and culturally particular “ocularcentric” regime, as some historians of philosophy have put it (Levin Reference Levin and Levin1993), one that construes semiosis and knowledge as a species of vision and imaging (Rorty Reference Rorty1979; Judovitz Reference Judovitz and Levin1993).Footnote 13 Consider, for example, some of the visual language in Peirce’s remarks on the index:

The index asserts nothing; it only says “There!” It takes hold of our eyes, as it were, and forcibly directs them to a particular object, and there it stops.

(Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 3.361)

… which like a Demonstrative pronoun, or a pointing finger, brutely direct the mental eyeballs of the interpreter to the object in question, which in this case cannot be given by independent reasoning.

(Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 8.350; also see Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 8.41).Footnote 14

For Heidegger, it is through such an ocularcentric formulation that Being comes to be articulated in modernity as representation (and denuded as simple beings); that is, that which “is” becomes that which can be made present to a subject as an image-object (Rorty Reference Rorty1979; Staten Reference Staten1984). Underwriting the writings of SAE thinkers from Plato and Aristotle to Descartes, Husserl, Saussure, and beyond, this metaphysics—or semiotic ideology—has treated Being as the immediated beginning and end of thought and reason, normatively privileging the self-present, self-identical, and the origin over absence, difference, and mediation (Derrida Reference Derrida and Spivak1976). This ontology contrasts with what Heidegger describes as an alternate metaphysics of presence: that of the pre-Platonic Greeks, for whom being (“what-is”) is less that which is looked upon by man as representation or as perceptually co-present object than that which looks upon man himself, which “rises up and opens itself” and “comes upon man” (Heidegger Reference Heidegger, Young and Haynes[1938] 2002, 68), and which in its presencing grabs and attaches itself to and in him (Derrida Reference Derrida, Kamuf, Rottenberg, Caws and Caws[1980] 2002, 109; cf. Nakassis Reference Nakassis2017b).

The primal pointing finger, in this classic representationalist metaphysics, then, doesn’t just render the object present as an object; it serves it up to us as an image of itself, as something to be seen so that it can be more immediately and truly known, to the eyes if not the transcendental mind (cf. Peirce’s “mental eyeballs”). And indeed, at the anxious limit of this account of the origins of conceptual thought—where seeing a present token-being enables the Object’s essence/type to be “seen” by the mind—the Form of the Object, its identity, and its Being are secured and purified, if always open to the haunting risk of mediation that this purification keeps at bay.Footnote 15

And herein is the irony with which we began, for it is against this enclosure and its variably cloaked, if still transparent yearning for immediation that indexicality rebels, be it in the hands of Peirce in his critiques of Descartes and Kant, or as grasped by linguistic anthropologists in critiques of structuralist approaches to language and culture, subject–object dualisms, and their related ideologies of representation.Footnote 16 The indexical sign—as with the prototypic pointing finger—depends on, and is defined by, Peirce’s Secondness: hence, its value can’t be fully specified solely by appeal to transcontextual rule, law, or essence, but only ever relative to its particular contexts of use, that is, to other arrays of sign-tokens that, in their indexical co-relatedness, reflexively frame and determine the value/reference of such an indexical sign (if only for then, there, and them). As such, indexicality is always residually enmeshed in that (Aristotelian) Matter that eludes Form, in that materiality that eludes “meaning,” even as it, in matter of fact, has form and is meaningful.

But if indexicality gives itself over in this way to a distributed, non-self-presentist account of mediation and if it does so by an appeal to and desire for co-presence, real existence, and the like, then perhaps we can see the paradoxical ambivalence at work in the foundational critiques made through it. Indexicality forsakes a metaphysics of presence and idealist representationalism while, at the same time, promising to get us closer to phenomena in their actuality, to make them more present and epistemologically available to our social scientific gaze in ways that idealist representationalist approaches, alas, fail to deliver. This is indexicality’s ambivalent ground.

From the Fingertip to the Wrist: Ethnographies of Presence

We can detect in indexicality, and thus in linguistic anthropology, an implicit metaphysics of presence, making both of a piece with that which they have been devoted to critiquing. What are we to make of this? While I discuss one important upshot of this ambivalence in the next section, let me note here that to the extent that this ambivalence is problematic, it is because it remains tacit and untheorized, and thus unworked upon and undeveloped. This allows analysis to proceed as if indexicality stands on solid ground, as if its ground was self-evident when it is anything but.

My claim, however, is not that such a naïve appeal to and desire for presence is avowed by any linguistic anthropologist. Indeed, as I’ve suggested, the field is founded on disavowing any such appeal or desire. Rather, my point is that such disavowals rest on, and stand in tension with, tacit assumptions smuggled in by the notion of indexicality itself, assumptions regarding questions of presence, existence, and being that thereby risk reappearing in our analyses, if not in our theory. This structure of ambivalence repudiates that which thereby may return, continually holding the immediate and the self-present at a distance, even as we, in turn, are held by them.Footnote 17

Pointing out this ambivalence forces such seemingly self-evident categories to become reflexive objects of worry; and, more to the point, ethnographic objects of worry that prompt us to reexamine our analytic concepts, in this case, indexicality. Indexicality has, of course, been central to anthropological analyses of how presence is achieved and mediated in variegated cultural contexts.Footnote 18 Silverstein’s (Reference Silverstein2004, 626–27) masterful analysis of the Eucharist, for example, shows in semiotic detail how the presence of Christ is indexically manifest—as a function of an emergent, iconic diagrammaticity standing under a Biblical metapragmatics—through those comestibles (wafer, wine) that by their ingestion incorporate congregants, in a chiastic reversal, into the body of Christ. A particular kind of presence, here, is the achieved effect of the ritual’s iconic-indexical “dynamic figuration” in its historical and cultural context of real-time and cosmic unfolding.Footnote 19

But if one finding of these studies has been the multiplicity of metaphysics of presence and thus the multiplicity of ontologies, and if indexicality, as it stands, itself presumes some such metaphysics, then on what other grounds might we find and found indexicality? That is, how might we make a critical and reflexive ethnography of presence the basis of our analytic, conceptual work (namely, in theorizing indexicality)? Rather than assuming that we know what indexicality is so as to show how presence is realized, how can an openness to the question of presence—in all its ethnographic complexity—reformulate our conceptualization, and thus analytic use, of indexicality?

This is a question that I have recently broached in a study of cinematic images of so-called mass heroes in the south Indian film industry of Tamil Nadu, such as the “Superstar” and “King of Style” Rajinikanth (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2017b). Filmic images of such auratic, charismatic personages are, for their Tamil filmic audiences, not simply representations of fictive characters or even of the absent star-actor. Rather, they are often citationally figured by fans as akin to religious idols and other figures of sovereignty, which in a Hindu idiom of darśan transubstantiate with devotees through seeing and being seen. There is an ontological identity between screen image and its object (Rajinikanth, the Superstar). Every avatar-character “played” by Rajinikanth is Rajinikanth, performatively presenced in the moment of the image’s apperception. This presence is the basis for a “cine-political” potency (Prasad Reference Prasad2014); indeed, such stars are expected to and on occasion do translate their populist screen/star images into political “message” (Lempert and Silverstein Reference Lempert and Silverstein2012), segueing from their filmic worlds to elected political office.

The textuality of Rajinikanth’s films cultivate this politicized presence, with copious shots of Rajinikanth looking and pointing at, and speaking to, the audience, often in highly charged moments of thinly veiled allegorical political oration (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2017a), with the audience yelling back, clapping, whistling, and touching the screen in response. Such scenes do not simply put Rajinikanth into the co-presence of his audience. Dynamically figurating them as metonyms of the “masses,” and him as an exemplary co-member who is also their representative, in such scenes Rajinikanth performatively encompasses, in ways not unlike the Eucharist (though in inversion of it), the audience/polity into his body politic. When the vector of Rajinikanth’s index finger fixes on the camera/fourth wall, he is not simply pointing at the audience. He is touching and grabbing them, transporting and transmuting himself/them across the diaphanous membrane of the screen so as to englobe them in his being. Reconstructing the indexical ground of such gestures and their presencing effects, I argue, requires ethnographically teasing out a metaphysics and metapragmatics of presence within and across film texts (since such presencing turns on an insistent citationality between films; see Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016a, 188–223) in relation to theatrical moments of screening and uptake. It is this metaphysics and metapragmatics (qua Rajinikanth’s being, his “mass”) that constitutively enables indexicality in such scenes. Here, the ground of indexicality is not a self-evident relation of causality, contiguity, or co-presence, but a highly mediated relation of encompassment, transposition, and incorporation. The point, however, is not that the category of indexicality is unnecessary for the analysis of Rajini’s finger (or for ethnographic inquiry more generally); it is absolutely critical. Rather, it is that to account for the indexicality of Rajini’s finger prompts our critical reflection on the category itself, enabling its further development for ethnographic analysis and theory.

The Dialectics of Indexicality and the Lexical Register of Linguistic Anthropology

One might take the argument presented so far as a deconstructive critique of indexicality. In certain measure, it is. But it is more a provocation to continue to think with the category, to keep unpacking it, to not presume that its faults and fault lines can simply be resolved or dismissed (Derrida Reference Derrida and Spivak1976, 13–14, 24; Nakassis Reference Nakassis2013c). The ambivalence of indexicality (and whatever problems this entails) is an opportunity and invitation, a site for analytic and theoretical refinement and productivity. This is implicitly realized, I contend in this section, in the relentless splitting and supplementing that the category has been subjected to by those who have theorized its implications.

Consider how indexicality is often bifurcated into two terms. Peirce, for example, distinguished “genuine” (or “perfect”) and “degenerate” indexes (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 5.75) for relations of relatively immediated dynamical (i.e., causal) connection and relations of mere spatiotemporal association (e.g., a punch in the face versus a pointing finger; Parmentier Reference Parmentier2016, 54, 70–71). Quine (Reference Quine1969, 39–40), for his part, distinguished “direct” and “deferred” ostension for acts individuating concrete referents at the end of the pointing vector (e.g., a rabbit) and those denoting some indirectly associated referent or quality (e.g., whiteness). Through a similar trope, Elinor Ochs’s (Reference Ochs, Duranti and Goodwin1992) “direct” and “indirect” indexes differentiate social indexes (e.g., of gender) based on degrees of exclusivity and specificity (i.e., in/directness) vis-à-vis their object (cf. Lefebvre Reference Lefebvre and Elkins2007, 231).Footnote 20 In each of these cases, the former of each pair is relatively more basic and immediated—more present, as it were—in relation to the latter, which is more mediated by or mediating of the context in which it is embedded (or embeds itself).

In this light, we might similarly consider Michael Silverstein’s important distinction of “presupposing” and “creative” (or “performative” or “entailing”) indexes, introduced in his 1976 “Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description” essay. Of the pair, the felicity of the first—exemplified in the essay by referential indexes—is a function of the representamen presupposing the independent existence of some aspect of the speech situation in which it occurs (namely, its object); by contrast, the latter—exemplified by nonreferential indexes—is a function of the index entailing the existence of some aspect of that context. This is not a hard split but a gradient, or better, two sides of a nonsynthesizing dialectic.

Of interest here is how “existence” is epistemologically and graphically bracketed in Silverstein’s text with consistency. In discussing relatively presupposing indexes (e.g., deictic phrases like this table) Silverstein notes that the referent of the token must be “identifiable, must “exist” cognitively, for the deictic itself to be interpretable” (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 33; my emphasis).Footnote 21 By contrast, relatively entailing indexes (e.g., deference indexes such as second-person pronouns in so-called T/V systems) bring “into sharp cognitive relief part of the context of speech” for participants and thus often “seem[] to be the very medium through which the relevant aspect of the context is made to ‘exist’” (ibid., 34; my emphasis; cf. Silverstein Reference Silverstein2004, 626). Here indexicality is re-grounded in cognition (cf. Peirce’s “mental eyeballs”) and the question of existence and co-presence bracketed out from the frame of analysis, deferred to their presence to thought, or to the context-oriented norm, or “rule of use,” which governs the meaningfulness of the sign.

This passage suggests a further distinction in addition to presupposing/entailing, referential/nonreferential indexes: between the localizability or globality of the indexical act (also see Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 49). The felicity of some indexical acts is (seemingly) relatively more localizable “in” a particular segmentable form in relation to its context (e.g., a relatively presupposing referential act of deixis). By contrast, other indexical acts involve relatively more distributed, global arrays of signs. The latter is the case with nonreferential entailing indexicalities (e.g., signs of deference), whose entailments are less the effect of the particular “salient” or “overt” sign in question (e.g., a pronoun) than the total effect of a textual configuration of indexical signs (e.g., the pronoun, previous/subsequent address practices, bodily hexis, etc.). Speakers, however, tend to focus on such a salient, overt sign rather than the total text-level indexicality (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 47–50, Reference Silverstein1981; Agha Reference Agha2007, 24, 286).

In short, certain forms of indexicality (presupposing, referential, localizable) are more likely to come before our “mental eyeballs” than others (entailing, nonreferential, distributed), and when directing our mind’s eyes (“brutely” or otherwise) the latter tend to present themselves as if they functioned on the model of the former. Hence the passage quoted above (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 34) hedges on the mediating power of entailing indexicalities by saying that overt and salient signs “seem[] to be the very medium …” (my emphasis) through which “existence” is manifest, for the reality of such entailed existence, as analysis reveals, is a function of much more than what appears to (explicit) consciousness.Footnote 22

In the few cases in Silverstein’s text where “existence” is not put in scare quotes, it is deferred to the fact of successful (i.e., “proper”) uses, in which case the analyst, like the sign user/perceiver, can assume there to have been an “actual” (ontological) dynamical connection of token-sign and object (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 33, 43–44; cf. later definitions of indexical presupposition as “appropriateness” to context [Silverstein Reference Silverstein2003a, 193]).

In all these examples the ontological question of existence and co-presence is epistemologically relativized to cognition (and to the legisign, or “rule”/norm, of the index) and rhetorically distanced through scare quotes, even as it is tacitly put into play (if with some epistemological wiggle room) and assumed to be, in matter of fact, presumable upon. This assumption, of course, follows from the conceit of introducing indexicality in the first place: namely, to “anchor” language back into cultural praxis, into its actually existing contexts and events of use (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 24–25, Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 224–25; see n. 22). Through this conceit and its deferral, existence and presence are slipped in through the backdoor (through which the analyst subsequently follows close behind).

Notice the delicate, perhaps even knowing, dance of ambivalence. We find a hedging and deferral of the (ethnographic) question of “existence”—and its mediation by cognition and norms of use—and a positive commitment to its (analytic) promise. This deferral and avowal is diagrammed by Silverstein’s splitting of indexicality into token and type, presupposition and entailment, referential and nonreferential, and localizable and configurational, wherein, as above, the former of each pair presumes upon a more immediated relation of existence relative to the latter, which is both more mediating and mediated.

Or perhaps not so delicate and very knowing. Indeed, in its use, such splitting of indexicality has been leveraged to unambiguously critique the semanticizing, representationalist tendencies that have haunted studies of the social aspects of language—where creative, nonreferential, and nonsegmentable and configurational (token-)indexicalities are reduced to presupposing, referentialist, segmentable and localizable (type-)indexicalities—as evinced for example, in Silverstein’s (see, e.g., Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b, Reference Silverstein2003a) withering reanalyses of classic studies of phonetic variation (Labov Reference Labov1972), explicit primary performativity (Austin Reference Austin1962), and honorification in pronominal systems (Brown and Gilman Reference Brown, Gilman and Sebeok1960) as various forms of folk ethnometapragmatics. In such cases, what mediates and constitutively enables indexicality (its cognitive reality and existence) misconstrues its actuality in the contexts of its occurrence, as present to (the “mental eyeballs” of) the semiotically sensitive analyst at least.

But if one half of this split seems to ideologically skew the phenomenon of indexicality, even as it constitutes it, the lesson is not to discard it for the other. Rather, the point is that there is an intrinsic dialectic here, one that can never rest on the immediacy of presence or existence (namely, “context”) and yet must presume upon it all the same (indeed, since the signs and their users do); which presumes upon the mediation of existence by semiosis and yet cannot take it at face value. And it is this tension, as I have argued, that is the Janus-faced ambivalence of indexicality itself, a tension mediating between immediacy and mediation.

This dialectic tension, however, is itself an indexical process, subject to the same ambivalence. This has also been tacitly registered in linguistic anthropology, worked through the copious analytic supplements to indexicality that the field has generated.Footnote 23 Such supplementing recognizes the inherently underdetermined, and hence mediated nature of indexicality as constitutive of indexicality’s actual effectivity in particular events of semiosis.

From the various terms that could similarly be worried, I consider Silverstein’s discussion of indexical order (Reference Silverstein1996, Reference Silverstein2003a) and, relatedly, metapragmatics (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, Reference Silverstein and Lucy1993a) and language ideology (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985b, Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b).

In a now classic article, first published twenty years after his “Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description” essay, Silverstein (Reference Silverstein1996, Reference Silverstein2003a) splits indexicality into “n-th” and “n+1-th” order indexes. Their dialectical relation comprises the earlier, related splitting of “presupposing” and “entailing” indexes and the supplements “metapragmatics” and “ideology.” They are related in the following way: any n-th order index (e.g., a second-person plural pronoun) indexically presupposes something of its context as a condition of its “appropriate” use (e.g., the existence and co-presence of a potential addressee), and in doing so may, under particular (co-)textual conditions, indexically entail something in the context of its use (e.g., honorification to singular addressee). As Silverstein shows, such entailments, however, are also inevitably a function of some metapragmatic, “ideological” regimentation, a “cultural construal of the n-th order usage” (Reference Silverstein2003a, 193–94) that may itself, through an interdiscursive process of enregisterment (or conventionalization), come to stand in a presupposing relation to the context (and n-th order indexicality) it itself reflexively mediates in the instance. Hence, to continue our example, the use of a second-person plural pronoun to honorificate a singular addressee can also function to index qualities of the speaker—as gentile, polite, old-fashioned, and so on. Such an n+1-th order indexicality, thus, stands as a “virtual” contextualization of the (n-th order) token index. This is in contrast to a (by implication) more “real,” “lower” order of contextualization; in our simplified example of the pronoun, to its “micro,” interactional text-in-context of prototypic face-to-face use.

Supplementing analytics like indexical order, metapragmatics, ideology show that the construability and efficacy of indexical acts are always mediated by some metafunction (as denoted by these analytics). Because the pragmatics of indexical signs are indeterminate out of context, they depend on some reflexive framework, or metapragmatics (or ideology, indexical order, etc.) to “fix” their otherwise shifty values (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b). Such metafunctions stand apart from and yet constitute indexical relations and processes. At the same time, these metafunctions are also emergent from, that is, are mediated by (or presuppose) the indexical processes they in turn dialectically mediate (or entail).Footnote 24 Ideologies and cultural construals of semiosis (n+1-th orders) respond to, rationalize, and unfold alongside and thus are motivated out of the indexicalities they thereby constitute in dialectical and historical turn. The pragmatics of n-th and the metapragmatics of n+1-th indexicalities presuppose and entail each other, each serving as the other’s conditions of possibility, actuality, and generality.

Here we see the splitting and supplementing tendencies arising from the ambivalence of indexicality brought into clear focus, where indexicality’s splitting implies its supplementation by some metaindexical (or metapragmatic) framing that is itself indexical, and thus similarly split. The splitting and supplementing of indexicality by linguistic anthropologists theorizes this dialectic—itself the unresolved ambivalence of indexicality, as I have been suggesting—and in doing so conserves something of that ambivalence. Telling in Silverstein’s Reference Silverstein1996/Reference Silverstein2003a article is how the hedging around “existence” and the deferral to cognition in the 1976 essay more or less disappears. Instead, the scare quotes and references to cognition are substituted for by the analytic supplements metapragmatics, ideology, and indexical order, in effect, internalizing that ambivalence to these dialectics of indexicality (even as it thereby externalizes cognition back into the social reality of such metafunctionalities). Consider, for example, how the notion of an indexical order imagines a stratified, even stratigraphic, layering of indexicalities with the more basic, originary indexicalities (and contextualizations) at a “lower,” more “micro” (face-to-face) and more present order entailing (the possibility of) “higher” and more “macro” “virtual” orders that, in dialectical turn, presuppose (and even replace or transform) those “lower” orders over interactional and historical time (cf. Silverstein Reference Silverstein2004, 650, Reference Silverstein2013, Reference Silverstein, Enfield, Kockelman and Sidnell2014a, 147, Reference Silverstein, Carr and Lempert2016; and see discussion below). While this framework troubles the representationalist ideologies and presentist metaphysics of the study of language, both persist, permanently problematized, in that framework’s very chronotopic form.

A dialectic view of indexicality implies that, in principle, it is indexicality “all the way down” (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b, 128). Yet if we could muster the courage to peer “all the way down” into the hoary recesses of this bottomless origo, we might surprisingly quickly find the primal scene of indexicality (rock bottom, as it were).Footnote 25 That trepidation, and perhaps vertiginous excitement, is, I have suggested, lexically (and textually) manifest in our continually progressive Eleatic splitting and supplementing of indexicality. As noted above, this doesn’t mean that indexicality is a naively physicalist or presentist concept unnecessary for serious ethnographic or semiotic inquiry. Exactly the opposite. It is precisely because of its ambivalences that indexicality has been, and continues to be, one of the most fertile and necessary tools to theorize semiosis and social life.

Semiotic Realism and the Ambivalent Dialectics of Immediacy/Mediation

In the lexical proliferation that has grown our subfield’s technical register—that is, these linked movements of splitting and supplementing—indexicality’s ambivalence vis-à-vis immediacy/mediation is both belied and betrayed, but also productively worried to theorize communicative action. Such splitting and supplementing take up indexicality while framing it as always mediated in ways that defer and problematize any simple notion of an immediated presence or existential connection; and yet, at the same time, both such movements conserve this very notion, they hold on to it, if only perhaps by letting it go underground and out of sight.

But as I have suggested, this ambivalence should be kept front and center, made visible and put under ethnographic scrutiny. Rather than something to be resolved or done away with, this compulsion to split, defer, and supplement can and should be pushed continually further. It is through this compulsion that our field has made progress and grown its conceptual riches. And this is why, I have suggested, the very ambivalent ground of indexicality is itself an important if perhaps underexplored site for empirical inquiry. Problematizing this ground, it seems to me, is implied by indexicality itself and by the ways in which our own pragmatically deconstructive engagements with it have mined and massaged its intrinsic ambivalence as the basis of its various dialectics (namely, presupposing/entailing, n-th/n+1-th, and each of these dialectics in dialectical relation to metapragmatics, ideology, indexical order, and so on).

In this, I think, is a larger lesson about the epistemology and ontology demanded by our semiotic realism (Reference PeirceEP 1:28–55; Silverstein Reference Silverstein2004, 651)—namely, our stance that semiosis is the basis of whatever we call reality (and our knowledge of it), and vice versa. From this semiotic realism, of which indexicality presents a metonymic object lesson, we see that mediation and immediacy are themselves phases or aspects of an irreducible dialectic, each presupposing the other, each entailing the other. This mutual relation makes each “side” of this dialectic both necessary and impossible. And it is this that gives rise to and drives semiosis itself, as a movement of immediacy toward ever-approaching mediation and from mediation to an ever-receding immediacy (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2013b). If indexicality as a concept is ambivalent, then, this is as it should be, for semiosis itself is ambivalent.

The grooves of this movement from Firstness to Thirdness, from Thirdness to Firstness is, as Peirce saw, Secondness. That is, actuality and existence are this movement, just as it is actuality that mediates the quality and possibility and generality and necessity of the worlds we inhabit and study. Perhaps it is not coincidental, then, that it is indexicality that has captivated linguistic anthropology’s “mental eyeballs” (though really, honed its disciplinary habits of semiosis: research, writing, reading, and teaching), for the ambivalence of indexicality is itself a perfect indexical (!) icon of the potencies and generalities, and thus reality, of semiosis as such.

One of the signature contributions of linguistic anthropology, exemplified in and developed by the work of Michael Silverstein, is not just to offer an analytical language to theorize this ambivalence and dialectic motility, but in doing so making both the driving engine of our own intellectual practice. As a semiotic practice spurred on by ethnographic engagements in worlds of Secondness (i.e., as a social science), linguistic anthropology has turned its own thought around this ambivalence, generating with each turn (or better, spiral) more and more developed interpretants of this particular ground. Looking back on this semiotic chain of interpretants as a way to look forward to their futures, Michael Silverstein has been a foundation and guiding light, providing pointed examples and real riches of analysis and critique. No doubt he will continue to provide us with all of the above in the years to come.

Footnotes

A number of the arguments in this essay were first articulated in an earlier paper, published in emended form as Nakassis (2017b). That earlier paper’s readers provided critical feedback to improve the arguments in this current article. They are Christopher Ball, Lily Chumley, Daniel Morgan, Keith Murphy, Richard Parmentier, and Justin Richland. Michael Lempert, Summerson Carr, Julie Chu, Jennifer Cole, and Paul Manning read a draft of this article and suggested ways to improve its flaws. Finally, thanks to Michael Silverstein, to whom this article is dedicated, whose semiotic concepts, scholarly example, and strong martinis have generously fortified many minds and spirits—including my own—over the years.

1. Indexicality, of course, is one small part of Peirce’s capacious account of the nature of semiosis, and more particularly, of logic and reasoning. That for Peirce indexicality (and the other sign functions) has no particular connection with language is not coincidental vis-à-vis why the term has been so productive for linguistic anthropology—which is also perhaps to say, why the term and the semiotic relation it denotes has had such a problematic status within linguistics and the philosophy of language (as discussed in the main text below).

2. In this essay, I differentiate between representation—which when otherwise unmodified has a neutral sense, denoting standing-for relations—and representationalist or representationalism—by which I denote a particular semiotic ideology concerning the nature of representation.

3. For Whorf (Reference Whorf and Carroll[1939] 1956), the “European” in “Standard Average European” denotes a group of (geographically and genetically related) languages that share a set of grammatical features and fashions of speaking (cf. Indo-European), which, as he pointed out, have motivated a number of familiar ontological (or rather, ontologized) conceptualizations within “Western” philosophy (such as form/substance, time/space). In elaborating on Whorf’s insight, Silverstein (Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein1981, Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b, Reference Silverstein and Kroskrity2000, Reference Silverstein2004) has shown how the dialectical processes by which such ideological motivation and cultural conceptualization emerge out of linguistic structure and practice itself accounts for the kinds of referentialist language ideologies advocated by SAE philosophy, as elaborated in the main text below.

4. For example, case marking and reference maintenance as dependent on a noun-phrase hierarchy whose apex and organizational logic are built around inherently metapragmatic indexicals (Silverstein Reference Silverstein1972, Reference Silverstein and Dixon1976a, Reference Silverstein1985c, Reference Silverstein and Hickmann1987, Reference Silverstein and Van1993c, Reference Silverstein1995); grammatical paradigms such as voice (Silverstein Reference Silverstein1978b) and person and gender (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b) as diachronically transformed by (non)referential indexicalities; or empty categories as poetic structures of textuality that mediate (inter)sentential structure (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Schiffrin1985d). These examples are not meant to be exhaustive, and many more topics by many more linguistic anthropologists could be included here; for the sake of space, and in the spirit of this special issue, I only provide references to Silverstein’s work, which others in the field have since built upon.

6. This is emphatically not to say that langue is not distinguishable from parole (or denotation from indexicality, form from function, competence from performance), or that langue can be reduced to parole (or form to function, etc.), but simply that one cannot think, or theorize, one without the other insofar as they exist in an inherently dialectical relation. On this point, see Silverstein (Reference Silverstein1975, 49; Reference Silverstein1986, 497, 512); cf. Silverstein (Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 206–11, 213–14, 228; Reference Silverstein and Hickmann1987, 130; Reference Silverstein2004, 622 n. 2).

7. Some important examples from Silverstein’s publications include deixis (Silverstein Reference Silverstein1972, 375–76; Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b; Reference Silverstein and Saville-Troike1978a); the evenemential and poetic nature of interaction and (con)textuality (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Schiffrin1985d, Reference Silverstein, Auer and DiLuzio1992, Reference Silverstein and Sawyer1998a, Reference Silverstein2003b; Silverstein and Urban Reference Silverstein, Urban, Silverstein and Urban1996); language acquisition (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a) and processing (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Beal1993b); the semiotics of ritual (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Lucy1993a, Reference Silverstein2004) and performativity (Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Saville-Troike1978a, Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein and Hickmann[1980] 1987, Reference Silverstein and Hickmann1987, Reference Silverstein2004); linguistic variation and speech registers (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b, Reference Silverstein2003a, Reference Silverstein, Lacoste, Leimgruber and Breyer2014b, Reference Silverstein2015); reflexivity in language (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein and Lucy1993a, Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b); cultural conceptualization and linguistic relativity (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979, Reference Silverstein1981, Reference Silverstein and Kroskrity2000, Reference Silverstein2004); and indexical linkages across speech events (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2005a, Reference Silverstein2013).

8. Here again note the significance for linguistic anthropology of the fact that indexicality—as an analytic indifferent to modality or medium—was coined by a philosopher who critiqued logic and philosophy for too closely hemming to language as the model for thought (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and WeissCP 2.211; Parmentier Reference Parmentier2016, 4). See n. 1.

9. It is of note that Silverstein’s discussions tend not to make finger pointing the primal scene of indexicality (or the basis for propositional acts of reference) but the reflexively (i.e., metapragmatically) regimented speech event, with its “indexical-denotationals” (shifters such as personal pronouns [Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 227; Reference Silverstein and Hickmann1987]), even if indexicality is still prototypically taken as a (metaphoric/generalized) “pointing-to.”

10. John Haviland (Reference Haviland and McNeill2000, 19) has called it, in another context, the “primeval home” of gesture study.

11. This is more complex, since with philosophers like Aristotle, Husserl, and Frege the pointing finger only refers to a token-being, whereas formal logic and language—on these philosophers’ accounts—aspire to capture the essence of the object-as-Form (Staten Reference Staten1984), to which only full-blown, “pure” semantico-referential language will ultimately do.

12. Gesture also serves, provocatively and in ways that run against this representationalist enclosure, in Fanon’s portrait of the origin of the racialized subject. Fanon (Reference Fanon and Philcox[1952] 2008, 89) writes:

Look, a Negro! I came into the world imbued with the will to find a meaning in things, my spirit filled with the desire to attain to the source of the world, and then I found that I was an object in the midst of other objects. Sealed into that crushing objected objecthood … But just as I get to the other slope I stumble, and the Other fixes me with his gaze, his gestures, and attitude the same way you fix a preparation with a dye [Mais là-bas, juste à contrepente, je bute, et l’autre, par gestes, attitudes, regards, me fixe, dans le sens où l’on fixe un préparation par un colorant]. … I exploded. Now the fragments have been put together again by another self.

13. If etymology bears revelance: indexicality and deixis both come from an Indo-European root that emerges in Greek for words to show (deixis) and Latin for verbs of speech (dicere), as well as the term digitus (finger), indicating the close etymological link in SAE languages between fingers and speech, showing and speaking. As Bühler ([1934] Reference Bühler and Goodwin1990, 44) notes, all such terms are related to the “domain of the visible” (also see Tyler Reference Tyler1984).

14. The differences, of course, between Peirce and the tradition of presentist philosophy that Derrida and Heidegger work within are many. In this context, most important is that for Peirce indexicality involves the Secondness of the ground between token-representamen and object rather than some ideality or self-presence of/to thought. Further, experience for Peirce, as Derrida (Reference Derrida and Spivak1976, 48–50) himself notes, is never self-present but only ever another sign, making his phenomenology (or “phaneroscopy,” as Peirce termed it) necessarily semiotic.

15. As told by Heidegger and Derrida, the history of philosophy is guided by a yearning to reduce indexicality to the ideality of the symbol and the self-evidence of the icon, and, in the face of this impossible wish, to resort to the disavowal and exteriorization of indexicality from its field of vision/knowledge (cf. Bar-Hillel Reference Bar-Hillel1954; Garfinkel and Sacks Reference Garfinkel, Sacks, McKinney and Tiryakian1970; Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Auer and DiLuzio1992, 55–56).

16. It is on this point that linguistic anthropology and Derridean deconstruction are allied; indeed, différance and Derrida’s other “paleonymics” problematize the same semiotic ideologies (or “metaphysics,” as Derrida calls them) that indexicality does, and in similar ways with similar conclusions; this convergence ends with this critical, theoretical discourse, however, given important methodological (and thus analytic and theoretical) differences between these two approaches (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2013a, Reference Nakassis2013c).

17. We might notice, for example, how we often insist on, and fetishize, the irreducibility of “face-to-face” interaction (Reyes Reference Reyes2014, 370; Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Enfield, Kockelman and Sidnell2014a, 147; Bauman Reference Bauman, Carr and Lempert2016) and the now not-so-neglected “situation” (Manning Reference Manning2001); how our concepts of exploding language into multimodality inevitably end up simply adding the visual and the gestural to our denotationally grounded transcripts. (Here we can note the centrality of recording technologies to capture presence and provide realist evidentiary certainty.) We can similarly point to recent symptomatic turns to the materiality of semiosis as a perceived salve against the field’s tendency to linguistic idealism (Hull Reference Hull2012; Nakassis Reference Nakassis2013b).

19. In a recent essay, Silverstein (Reference Silverstein, Carr and Lempert2016, 196–97) suggests that the presencing entailed by the Eucharist exemplifies the more general dialectics of (meta)indexicality that he first theorized twenty years earlier (Silverstein Reference Silverstein1996; see the next section for discussion). We might ask, given that Christian metaphysics are one among many, can we open up (and reevaluate) indexicality’s grounds, and dialectics, through ethnographies of other kinds of presence?

20. Other splittings we might note include referential (“duplex”) and nonreferential (“pure”) indexes (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 29–30); categorical and statistical indexes (Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Mertz and Parmentier1985b); indexical figures and grounds (Hanks Reference Hanks1990; cf. Bühler [1934] Reference Bühler and Goodwin1990); indexical tokens (as/in “happenings”) and types/legisigns (as/in “text”; Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Auer and DiLuzio1992); indexical sources and targets (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2005a); and indexical origos and focuses (Agha Reference Agha1993; Fleming Reference Fleming2016). Many of these, needless to say, intersect and/or describe overlapping phenomena as discussion in the main text below suggests.

21. Silverstein (Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 220; cf. Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 27) is more explicit elsewhere, saying that “at the functional level of true reference, the sign purports to index (be in spatiotemporal—“real world”—contiguity, direct or indirect with) at least one and perhaps more existing individuals. We claim nothing for the spatiotemporal continuity of such objects or their actuality independent of the act of true reference. We claim merely that such a functional sign qua sign presupposes the conditions at the moment of use.” Examples include “pointing gesture[s] with lips or finger, or any linguistic equivalent” (1985a, 220).

22. This implies, however, that for relatively entailing indexical signs whose effects are globally mediated, there are indexicalities between co-present token-signs within the emergent text-in-context that have an existence and reality that is not quite present to the mind (even if, however, registered in some manner), that is, without a full “cognitive ‘existence’” to participants in the event (though cognitively real for analysts, with recursive regress entailed therein; cf. Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b, 131). As with the appeal to “proper” usage of relatively presupposing indexes (see main text below), this gap allows the analyst to transcend the bracketed question of presumed “existence” (i.e., the mediation by cognition or the legisign of the index) to an analytically present moment of interpreting the actuality of events (i.e., the mediation of cognition through token-indexes). Tracing that gap’s entailments in later events of semiosis (as ideologically mediated/mediating metapragmatics) affords a further “in” to the study of semiosis (though this angle is not yet explored in Silverstein [Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b]; see discussion of “indexical orders” in main text below).

23. In addition to those I discuss in the main text below, we can note supplementary analytics such as deictic fields (Bühler [1934] Reference Bühler and Goodwin1990); background language (Quine Reference Quine1960; Reference Quine1969); indexical frames (Hanks Reference Hanks1990); constitutive relations (Ochs Reference Ochs, Duranti and Goodwin1992); entextualization (Briggs and Bauman Reference Briggs and Bauman1992; Silverstein Reference Silverstein, Auer and DiLuzio1992; Silverstein and Urban Reference Silverstein, Urban, Silverstein and Urban1996); meta-indexicality (Lee Reference Lee1997); enregisterment (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2003a, Reference Silverstein, Carr and Lempert2016; Agha Reference Agha2007); iconization (Irvine and Gal Reference Irvine, Gal and Kroskrity2000) or rhematicization (Gal Reference Gal2005); and dicentization (Ball Reference Ball2014); as well as variants of language ideology: semiotic ideology, media ideology, voice ideology, etc. (see Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016b, 333–34). We can similarly consider Silverstein’s (Reference Silverstein, Basso and Selby1976b, 44–45; Reference Silverstein, Cline, Hanks and Hofbauer1979; Reference Silverstein and Hickmann[1980] 1987; Reference Silverstein and Hickmann1987) discussion of pragmatic function1 and function2. In each case, such supplements theorize the ways in which the dialectical ambivalence of indexicality is metasemiotically mediated.

24. That is, such metafunctions, as indexical phenomena themselves, are liable to this ambivalent splitting, as seen in the Janus-faced nature of language ideologies (as secondary rationalizations and causally efficacious regimentations of linguistic practices and forms) or in Silverstein’s (Reference Silverstein and Wertsch1985a, 218–31) discussion of “naturally occurring” and “virtual” metapragmatics.

25. While this is certainly a result of the semantico-referentialist genealogy of linguistic cases that Silverstein has masterfully reanalyzed over his career, it is of interest that in going “down” the orders we quickly bottom out: face-to-face conversational mechanics (e.g., adjacency pair parts), inherently referential deictics (e.g., personal pronouns), phonetic substances (sociolinguistic variables). The full quote above from Silverstein (Reference Silverstein, Schieffelin, Woolard and Kroskrity1998b, 128) is: “We ought, perhaps, to resign ourselves to enjoying the fact that it’s indexicality all the way down, that in any sociocultural phenomenon nothing is manifest beyond this indexicality except semanticoreferential language and its further developments.”

References

Agha, Asif. 1993. “Grammatical and Indexical Convention in Honorific Discourse.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 3 (2): 131–63.10.1525/jlin.1993.3.2.131CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agha, Asif. 2007. Language and Social Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1962. How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ball, Christopher. 2014. “On Dicentization.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 24 (2): 151–73.10.1111/jola.12046CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua. 1954. “Indexical Expressions.Mind 63:359–79.10.1093/mind/LXIII.251.359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bate, John Bernard. 2009. Tamil Oratory and the Dravidian Aesthetic. New York: Columbia University Press.10.7312/bate14756CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bauman, Richard. 2016. “Projecting Presence: Aura and Oratory in William Jennings Bryan’s Presidential Races.” In Scale: Dimensions and Discourse in Social Life, ed. Carr, E. S. and Lempert, M., 25–51. Oakland: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Briggs, Charles, and Bauman, Richard. 1992. “Genre, Intertextuality, and Social Power.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 2 (2): 131–72.10.1525/jlin.1992.2.2.131CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R., and Gilman, A.. 1960. “The Pronouns of Power and Solidarity.” In Style in Language, ed. Sebeok, T., 253–76. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Bühler, Karl. 1990. Theory of Language. Trans. Goodwin, D.. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/fos.25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1976. Of Grammatology. Trans. Spivak, G.. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. (1980) 2002. “Envoi.” In Psyche, vol. 1, ed. Kamuf, P. and Rottenberg, E., trans. Caws, P. and Caws, M., 94–128. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Fanon, Franz. (1952) 2008. Black Skin, White Masks. Trans. Philcox, R.. New York: Grove.Google Scholar
Fleming, Luke. 2016. “Of Referents and Recipients: Pohnpeian Humiliatives and the Functional Organization of Austronesian Honorific Registers.Berkeley Linguistics Society 42:293–312.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob. (1892) 1980. “On Sense and Meaning.” In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. Geach, P. and Black, M., 56–78. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gal, Susan. 2005. “Language Ideologies Compared: Metaphors of Public/Private.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 15 (1): 23–37.10.1525/jlin.2005.15.1.23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, Harold, and Sacks, Harvey. 1970. “On the Formal Structure of Practical Actions.” In Theoretical Sociology, ed. McKinney, J. and Tiryakian, E., 338–66. New York: Appleton Century Crofts.Google Scholar
Hanks, William. 1990. Referential Practice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Haviland, John. 2000. “Pointing, Gesture Spaces, and Mental Maps.” In Language and Gesture, ed. McNeill, D., 13–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511620850.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, Martin. (1938) 2002. “The Age of the World Picture.” In Off the Beaten Track, ed. and trans. Young, J. and Haynes, K., 57–72. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hull, Matthew. 2012. Government of Paper: The Materiality of Bureaucracy in Urban Pakistan. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Irvine, Judith and Gal, Susan. 2000. “Language Ideology and Linguistic Differentiation.” In Regimes of Language, ed. Kroskrity, P., 35–84. Santa Fe, NM: School of American Research Press.Google Scholar
Jakobson, Roman. 1953. “Chapter 2.” In Results of the Conference of Anthropologists and Linguists, by C. Lévi-Strauss, R. Jakobson, C. F. Voeglin, and T. Sebeok, 11–21. Memoir 8 of the International Journal of American Linguistics. Baltimore, MD: Waverly.Google Scholar
Jakobson, Roman. (1957) 1984. “Shifters, Verbal Categories, and the Russian Verb.” In Russian and Slavic Grammar: Studies, 1931–1981, ed. Waugh, L. and Halle, M., 41–58. Berlin: Mouton.10.1515/9783110822885.41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judovitz, Dalia. 1993. “Vision, Representation, and Technology in Descartes.” In Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision, ed. Levin, D., 63–86. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Keane, Webb. 2003. “Semiotics and the Social Analysis of Material Things.” Language and Communication 23 (3–4): 409–25.10.1016/S0271-5309(03)00010-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Labov, William. 1972. Sociolinguistic Patterns. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Lee, Benjamin. 1997. Talking Heads. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Lefebvre, Martin. 2007. “The Art of Pointing: On Peirce, Indexicality, and Photographic Images.” In Photography Theory, ed. Elkins, J., 220–44. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lempert, Michael, and Silverstein, Michael. 2012. Creatures of Politics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Leone, Massimo, and Parmentier, Richard. 2014. “Representing Transcendence: The Semiosis of Real Presence.” Signs and Society 2 (S1): S1–S23.10.1086/674529CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, David. 1993. “Introduction.” In Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision, ed. Levin, D., 1–29. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, Stephen. 2004. “Deixis.” In Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. Horn, L. and Ward, G., 97–121. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Manning, Paul. 2001. “On Social Deixis.Anthropological Linguistics 43 (1): 54–100.Google Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V. 2013a. “Citation and Citationality.Signs and Society 1 (1): 51–78.10.1086/670165CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2013b. “Materiality, Materialization.Hau 3 (3): 399–406.10.14318/hau3.3.022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2013c. “Para-s/cite, Parts I and II.” Semiotic Review, http://semioticreview.com.Google Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2016a. Doing Style: Youth and Mass Mediation in South India. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226327990.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2016b. “Linguistic Anthropology in 2015: Not the Study of Language.American Anthropologist 118 (2): 330–45.10.1111/aman.12528CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2017a. “Poetics of Praise and Cinematic Encompassment.” Working Papers of the Chicago Tamil Forum—Poesis/Politics of Language and Place in Tamilagam (May 25–27, 2017), http://chicagotamilforum.uchicago.edu.Google Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine V.. 2017b. “Rajini’s Finger, Indexicality, and the Metapragmatics of Presence.Signs and Society 5 (2): 201–42.10.1086/692128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ochs, Elinor. 1992. “Indexing Gender.” In Rethinking Context, ed. Duranti, A. and Goodwin, C., 335–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Parmentier, Richard. 2016. Signs and Society: Further Studies in Semiotic Anthropology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.10.2307/j.ctt2005snsCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perrino, Sabina. 2003. “Intimate Hierarchies and Qur’anic Saliva (Tefli): Textuality in a Senegalese Ethnomedical Encounter.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 12 (2): 225–59.10.1525/jlin.2002.12.2.225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1931–58. The Collected Papers of Charles S. Peirce. 8 vols. Ed. Hartshorne, Charles, Weiss, Paul, and A. W. Burks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press [cited as CP].Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S.. 1998. The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings. 2 vols. Ed. the Peirce Edition Project. Bloomington: Indiana University Press [cited as EP].Google Scholar
Prasad, M. Madhava. 2014. Cine-Politics. Chennai: Orient Blackswan.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard. 1969. “Ontological Relativity.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, 26–68. New York: Columbia University Press.10.7312/quin92204-003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reyes, Angela. 2014. “Linguistic Anthropology in 2013: Super-New-Big.American Anthropologist 116 (2): 366–78.10.1111/aman.12109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Saussure, Ferdinand de. (1916) 1986. Course in General Linguistics. Trans. Harris, R.. New York: Open Court.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1972. “Linguistic Theory: Syntax, Semantics, Pragmatics.Annual Review of Anthropology 1:349–82.10.1146/annurev.an.01.100172.002025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1975. “La Sémiotique jakobsonienne et l’anthropologie sociale.” L’Arc (Aix-en-Provence) 60:45–49.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1976a. “Hierarchy of Features and Ergativity.” In Grammatical Categories in Australian Languages, ed. Dixon, R. M. W., 112–71. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1976b. “Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description.” In Meaning in Anthropology, ed. Basso, K. and Selby, H., 11–55. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1978a. “Cultural Prerequisites for Grammatical Analysis.” In Linguistics and Anthropology, ed. Saville-Troike, M., 139–51. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1978b. “Deixis and Deducibility in a Wasco-Wishram Passive of Evidence.Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 4:238–53.10.3765/bls.v4i0.3167CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1979. “Language Structure and Linguistic Ideology.” In The Elements: A Parasession on Linguistic Units and Levels, ed. Cline, R., Hanks, W., and Hofbauer, C., 193–247. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. (1980) 1987. “The Three Faces of ‘Function’: Preliminaries to a Psychology of Language.” In Social and Functional Approaches to Language and Thought, ed. Hickmann, M., 17–38. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1981. “Limits of Awareness.” In Working Papers in Sociolinguistics 84, 2–31. Austin, TX: Southwest Educational Research Laboratory.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1985a. “The Functional Stratification of Language and Ontogenesis.” In Culture, Communication, and Cognition: Vygotskian Perspectives, ed. Wertsch, J., 205–35. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1985b. “Language and the Culture of Gender: At the Intersection of Structure, Usage, and Ideology.” In Semiotic Mediation, ed. Mertz, E. and Parmentier, R., 219–59. Orlando: Academic Press.10.1016/B978-0-12-491280-9.50016-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1985c. “Noun Phrase Categorial Markedness and Syntactic Parametricization.” In ESCOL ’85, 337–61. Columbus: Department of Linguistics, Ohio State University.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1985d. “On the Pragmatic ‘Poetry’ of Prose: Parallelism, Repetition, and Cohesive Structure in the Time Course of Dyadic Conversation.” In Meaning, Form, and Use in Context, ed. Schiffrin, D., 181–99. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1986. “Classifiers, Verb Classifiers, and Verbal Categories.Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 12:497–514.10.3765/bls.v12i0.1845CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1987. “Cognitive Implications of a Referential Hierarchy.” In Social and Functional Approaches to Language and Thought, ed. Hickmann, M., 125–64. Orlando: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1992. “The Indeterminacy of ‘Contextualization’: When Is Enough Enough.” In The Contextualization of Language, ed. Auer, P. and DiLuzio, A., 55–75. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/pbns.22.05silCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1993a. “Metapragmatic Discourse and Metapragmatic Function.” In Reflexive Language, ed. Lucy, J., 33–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511621031.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1993b. “Of Dynamos and Doorbells: Semiotic Modularity and the (Over)determination of Cognitive Representations.” In What We Think, What We Mean, and How We Say It: Parasession on the Correspondence of Conceptual, Semantic, and Grammatical Representations, ed. Beal, K. et al., 319–45. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1993c. “Of Nominatives and Datives: Universal Grammar from the Bottom Up.” In Advances in Role and Reference Grammar, ed. Van, R. Valin Jr., 465–98. Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1995. “Kiksht ‘Impersonals’ as Anaphors and the Predictiveness of Grammatical-Categorial Universals.Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 21:262–86.10.3765/bls.v21i1.1405CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1996. “Indexical Order and the Dialectics of Sociolinguistic Life.SALSA 3:266–95.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1998a. “The Improvisational Performance of Culture in Realtime Discursive Practice.” In Creativity in Performance, ed. Sawyer, R. K., 265–312. Greenwich, CT: Ablex.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 1998b. “The Uses and Utility of Ideology: A Commentary.” In Language Ideologies, ed. Schieffelin, B., Woolard, K., and Kroskrity, P., 123–45. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780195105612.003.0006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2000. “Whorfianism and the Linguistic Imagination of Nationality.” In Regimes of Language, ed. Kroskrity, P., 85–138. Santa Fe, NM: School of American Research Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2003a. “Indexical Order and the Dialectics of Sociolinguistic Life.” Language and Communication 23 (3–4): 193–229.10.1016/S0271-5309(03)00013-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2003b. Talking Politics: The Substance of Style from Abe to W. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2004. “‘Cultural’ Concepts and the Language-Culture Nexus.Current Anthropology 45 (5): 621–52.10.1086/423971CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2005a. “Axes of -Evals: Token versus Type Interdiscursivity.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 15 (1): 6–22.10.1525/jlin.2005.15.1.6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2005b. “Languages/Cultures Are Dead! Long Live the Linguistic-Cultural.” In Unwrapping the Sacred Bundle, ed. Segal, D. and Yanagisako, Sylvia, 99–125. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.10.1215/9780822386841-005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2013. “Discourse and the No-thing-ness of Culture.Signs and Society 1 (2): 327–66.10.1086/673252CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2014a. “Denotation and the Pragmatics of Language.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Linguistic Anthropology, ed. Enfield, N., Kockelman, P., and Sidnell, J., 128–57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139342872.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2014b. “The Race from Place: Dialect Eradication and Terroir of Linguistic ‘Authenticity.’.” In Indexing Authenticity, ed. Lacoste, V., Leimgruber, J., and Breyer, T., 159–87. Berlin: de Gruyter.10.1515/9783110347012.159CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2015. “How Language Communities Intersect: Is ‘Superdiversity’ an Incremental or Transformative Condition?Language and Communication 44:7–18.10.1016/j.langcom.2014.10.015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2016. “Semiotic Vinification and the Scaling of Taste.” In Scale: Dimensions and Discourse in Social Life, ed. Carr, E. S. and Lempert, M., 185–212. Oakland: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael, and Urban, Greg. 1996. “The Natural History of Discourse.” In Natural Histories of Discourse, ed. Silverstein, M. and Urban, G., 1–17. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stasch, Rupert. 2011. “Ritual and Oratory Revisited: The Semiotics of Effective Action.Annual Review of Anthropology 40:159–74.10.1146/annurev-anthro-081309-145623CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staten, Harry. 1984. Wittgenstein and Derrida. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
Tomasello, Michael. 2008. Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/7551.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tyler, Stephen. 1984. “The Vision Quest in the West, or What the Mind’s Eye Sees.Journal of Anthropological Research 40 (1): 23–40.10.1086/jar.40.1.3629688CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vygotsky, Lev. 1978. Mind in Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Whorf, Benjamin Lee. (1939) 1956. “The Relation of Habitual Thought and Behavior to Language.” In Language, Thought, and Reality, ed. Carroll, J., 134–59. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar