Paul Pierson's “Not Just What, but When: Timing and
Sequence in Political Processes” is a fitting centerpiece for this
symposium. The article takes up themes that have occupied students of
comparative politics for some time now and moves the debate decisively
forward.For earlier efforts to assess the role of
sequencing and timing in politics, see for example, Harsanyi's discussion
of “static” and “dynamic” explanation (J. Harsanyi,
“Explanation and Comparative Dynamics in Social Science,”
Behavioral Science 5 (1960): 136–45); also Verba's early
attempts within the context of modernization theory to specify more precisely a
“sequential model” that linked outcomes within particular countries
to the sequence in which they encountered a set of putatively common challenges
(Sidney Verba, “Sequences and Development,” in Leonard Binder et
al., Crises and Sequences in Political Development [Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1971], 283–316). Tilly has dealt with related
issues of temporality and ordering; see Charles Tilly, “Future
History,” Theory and Society 17 (1988): 703–12; Tilly,
Big Structures, Large Processes, Huge Comparisons (New York: Russell
Sage Foundation, 1984); and Tilly, “The Time of States,” Social
Research 61 (1994): 269–95. Schmitter and Santiso have also addressed
these topics (Philippe C. Schmitter and Javier Santiso, “Three Temporal
Dimensions to the Consolidation of Democracy,” International Political
Science Review 19 (1998): 69–92). And of course, Pierson's
agenda picks up on themes long advocated by the editors of this journal to take
temporality seriously (Karen Orren and Stephen Skowronek, “Beyond the
Iconography of Order: Notes for a ‘New' Institutionalism,” in
The Dynamics of American Politics, eds. Lawrence C. Dodd and Calvin
Jillson (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1994). Pierson's
overall message is that social phenomena are often better captured in
“moving pictures” that situate a given outcome within a broader
temporal framework than in “snapshots” based on cross-sectional
data. He constructs a convincing case for this proposition and along the way he
also makes progress in rendering the ubiquitous but vague concept of path
dependence more useful.For other treatments of
this issue see Stephen D. Krasner, “Sovereignty: An Institutional
Perspective,” Comparative Political Studies 21 (1988):
66–94; Timur Kuran, “The Tenacious Past: Theories of Personal and
Collective Conservatism,” Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization 10 (1988): 143–71; Douglass C. North, Institutions,
Institutional Change and Economic Performance (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1990); and James Mahoney, “Uses of Path Dependence in
Historical Sociology,” unpubl. ms., Brown University,
1999.