Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T05:20:09.964Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The role of meta-analyses and umbrella reviews in assessing the harms of psychotropic medications: beyond qualitative synthesis

Part of: Editorials

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 July 2018

M. Solmi*
Affiliation:
Department of Neurosciences, University of Padua, Padua, Italy University Hospital of Padua, Padua, Italy Padova Neuroscience Center, University of Padua, Padua, Italy
C. U. Correll
Affiliation:
The Zucker Hillside Hospital, Department of Psychiatry, Northwell Health, Glen Oaks, NY, USA Hofstra Northwell School of Medicine, Department of Psychiatry and Molecular Medicine, Hempstead, NY, USA Charité Universitätsmedizin, Department of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, Berlin, Germany
A. F. Carvalho
Affiliation:
Centre for Addiction & Mental Health (CAMH), Toronto, Ontario, Canada Department of Psychiatry, University of Toronto, Toronto, ON, Canada
J. P. A. Ioannidis
Affiliation:
Department of Medicine, Stanford Prevention Research Center, Stanford, CA, USA Department of Health Research and Policy, Stanford University School of Medicine, Stanford, CA, USA Meta-Research Innovation Center at Stanford, Stanford University, Stanford, CA, USA Department of Statistics, Stanford University School of Humanities and Sciences, Stanford, CA, USA
*
Author for correspondence: Marco Solmi, E-mail: marco.solmi83@gmail.com
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

ὠφελέειν, ἢ μὴ βλάπτειν (Primum non nocere) – Hιppocrates’ principle should still guide daily medical prescribing. Therefore, assessing evidence of psychopharmacologic agents’ safety and harms is essential. Randomised controlled trials (RCTs) and observational studies may provide complementary information about harms of psychopharmacologic medications from both experimental and real-world settings. It is considered that RCTs provide a better control of confounding variables, while observational studies provide evidence from larger samples, longer follow-ups, in more representative samples, which may be more reflective of real-life clinical scenarios. However, this may not always hold true. Moreover, in observational studies, safety data are poorly or inconsistently reported, precluding reliable quantitative synthesis in meta-analyses. Beyond individual studies, meta-analyses, which represent the highest level of ‘evidence’, can be misleading, redundant and of low methodological quality. Overlapping meta-analyses sometimes even reach different conclusions on the same topic. Meta-analyses should be assessed systematically. Descriptive reviews of reviews can be poorly informative. Conversely, ‘umbrella reviews’ can use a quantitative approach to grade evidence. In this editorial, we present the main factors involved in the assessment of psychopharmacologic agents’ harms from individual studies, meta-analyses and umbrella reviews. Study design features, sample size, number of the events of interest, summary effect sizes, p-values, heterogeneity, 95% prediction intervals, confounding factor adjustment and tests of bias (e.g., small-study effects and excess significance) can be combined with other assessment tools, such as AMSTAR and GRADE to create a framework for assessing the credibility of evidence.

Type
Editorial
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Introduction

Psychopharmacologic agents may differ in both efficacy and safety (Leucht et al., Reference Leucht, Cipriani, Spineli, Mavridis, Orey, Richter, Samara, Barbui, Engel, Geddes, Kissling, Stapf, Lassig, Salanti and Davis2013; Solmi et al., Reference Solmi, Murru, Pacchiarotti, Undurraga, Veronese, Fornaro, Stubbs, Monaco, Vieta, Seeman, Correll and Carvalho2017; Cipriani et al., Reference Cipriani, Furukawa, Salanti, Chaimani, Atkinson, Ogawa, Leucht, Ruhe, Turner, Higgins, Egger, Takeshima, Hayasaka, Imai, Shinohara, Tajika, Ioannidis and Geddes2018). While by law all medications that make their way to the market are believed to be more efficacious than placebo (Cipriani et al., Reference Cipriani, Furukawa, Salanti, Chaimani, Atkinson, Ogawa, Leucht, Ruhe, Turner, Higgins, Egger, Takeshima, Hayasaka, Imai, Shinohara, Tajika, Ioannidis and Geddes2018), they may also carry variable risks of harms (Leucht et al., Reference Leucht, Cipriani, Spineli, Mavridis, Orey, Richter, Samara, Barbui, Engel, Geddes, Kissling, Stapf, Lassig, Salanti and Davis2013; Cipriani et al., Reference Cipriani, Furukawa, Salanti, Chaimani, Atkinson, Ogawa, Leucht, Ruhe, Turner, Higgins, Egger, Takeshima, Hayasaka, Imai, Shinohara, Tajika, Ioannidis and Geddes2018) and sometimes these risks may limit tolerability of medications. Pharmacological trials’ sample sizes are estimated based on the desired power (often 0.8) to detect clinically relevant effect sizes in terms of efficacy-related outcomes, but not on outcomes related to harms, safety or tolerability. Hence, individual trials are often underpowered to inform about the overall safety and tolerability of the various psychopharmacological agents. Additionally, rarely specific rating scales are used to detect and quantify adverse effects and inferential statistics are generally reserved for efficacy outcomes. Conversely, observational studies assessing psychopharmacologic agents may include larger sample sizes, longer follow-ups and more representative samples, which may be more reflective of real-life clinical scenarios. However, this may not always hold true. Moreover, in observational studies, safety data may be poorly or inconsistently reported and methodological flaws, limitations and proneness to bias may inherently decrease their credibility. Observational data include a wide spectrum of designs with highly variable levels of rigour. For example, a few observational studies that aim to assess harms may be pre-registered at the time of a new drug approval and the data may be collected prospectively according to very meticulous definitions and data collection plans and then analysed according to the prespecified protocol. Conversely, most observational studies are entirely open to manipulation and may suffer from poor data quality and selectively reported analyses. Combining data from several observational studies and trials with meta-analytic approaches may provide a more accurate ‘big picture’ of extant data on the harms of prescribing psychotropics. However, if primary sources of evidence are methodologically poor, then simply synthesising evidence may lead to misleading conclusions (Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2017). Furthermore, while meta-analyses are typically regarded at the highest rank of evidence, they are exponentially increasing in number, often introducing more confusion than information to the literature, due to the low methodological standards of the published meta-analyses and, even more so, their included studies (Correll et al., Reference Correll, Rubio, Inczedy-Farkas, Birnbaum, Kane and Leucht2017), as well as redundancy, which may limit the clinical impact and the overall contribution to scientific knowledge or progress (Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2016; Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2017). It is important to comprehensively assess evidence from meta-analyses to minimise research waste (Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2009b, Reference Ioannidis2016).

While the availability of systematic reviews and meta-analyses of harms has been rather low (Papanikolaou and Ioannidis, Reference Papanikolaou and Ioannidis2004), more recently the field has witnessed a renewed attention to the reporting of harms in single studies (Ioannidis et al., Reference Ioannidis, Evans, Gotzsche, O'Neill, Altman, Schulz, Moher and Group2004) and this has followed proposals to improve the standardisation of reporting in meta-analyses of harms (Zorzela et al., Reference Zorzela, Loke, Ioannidis, Golder, Santaguida, Altman, Moher, Vohra and Group2016). Thus, systematic reviews and meta-analyses of harms, including meta-analyses of individual-level data, may become more prevalent in the literature in upcoming years.

This editorial provides a critical overview of several aspects to account for, when assessing the quality of evidence or when grading its credibility or certainty when focusing on harms associated with the use of psychopharmacologic agents (Table 1).

Table 1. Factors that may be considered in the assessment of the evidence on harms outcomes of pharmacological interventions from meta-analyses of observational or interventional studies

AMSTAR, Assessing the Methodological Quality of Systematic Reviews; optimal information size, total number of patients included in a systematic review is less than the number of patients generated by a conventional sample size calculation for a single adequately powered trial; RCT, randomised controlled trial; small study effect, when both largest study of the meta-analysis is more conservative and publication bias is present.

Research design

Observational and intervention studies may or may not agree on their estimates of risks of harms. Differences between estimates may in some circumstances be major, especially when absolute (i.e., non-adjusted) risks are considered (Papanikolaou et al., Reference Papanikolaou, Christidi and Ioannidis2006). Evidence from observational and intervention studies should thus be evaluated with different frameworks.

Somewhat stricter criteria must be applied to evidence from observational studies, as they are prone to more sources of bias as well as to several sources of confounding. For example, retrospective studies are particularly prone to recall bias, while gender, smoking, age, or ongoing treatment with various antipsychotics are typical confounding factors that may influence results from observational studies.

Moreover, the adequacy, accuracy and consistency of definitions of exposure, cases and controls need to be taken into careful consideration. For example, a positive screen for depression based on a screening tool may provide a less robust outcome than a diagnosis of a major depressive episode made according to DSM-5 criteria (i.e., through a validated structured diagnostic interview) (APA, 2013). In addition, the mere presence of depressive symptoms assessed with rating scales may not substantiate the actual presence of a major depressive episode. In analogy, a self-reported accelerated heart-beat would be less reliable than a diagnosis of tachyarrhythmia made by a physician. Similarly, a definition of controls based only on the lack of a current major depressive episode would provide a less homogeneous group than a comparison group comprising individuals with a current or lifetime history of major mental disorders.

Observational studies often attempt to establish causal inferences, but this is a notoriously challenging task. Prospective cohort studies may avoid reverse causality. For example, baseline exposure (i.e. smoking) cannot be caused by a subsequent outcome (i.e. cancer). However, methodological limitations of observational studies may preclude the establishment of firm causal inferences, whilst retrospective studies cannot even sort out the possibility of reverse causality. Mendelian randomisation studies may offer a design option that may have better chances of addressing causality. Yet Mendelian randomisation studies are not particularly well-suited to study medication harms.

On the other hand, RCTs are less prone to bias, but usually, they cannot enroll desired sample sizes compared with observational studies, at least partly due to more time-consuming assessments, stricter eligibility criteria, time and economic resources needed. Exposure, namely treatment, is by definition more straightforward in RCTs compared with observational studies. Also control groups, which may vary across RCTs and which can be active (i.e., in head-to-head trials) or placebo (Weihrauch and Gauler, Reference Weihrauch and Gauler1999), are clearly defined in RCTs. However, when adverse events are an outcome of interest, the sample size of individual RCTs is often too low and these studies or even meta-analyses aiming at synthesising evidence from these studies may be underpowered. Reporting also is often highly elliptical, partial, or biased (Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2009a).

In some scenarios, evidence exists from both observational studies and RCTs and this evidence ideally could be assessed together and juxtaposed. Consistency and convergence of the evidence from studies with both designs may reassure on the validity of certain associations (Papanikolaou et al., Reference Papanikolaou, Christidi and Ioannidis2006). For example, some previous umbrella reviews have assessed evidence from both types of study designs (Theodoratou et al., Reference Theodoratou, Tzoulaki, Zgaga and Ioannidis2014; Li et al., Reference Li, Meng, Timofeeva, Tzoulaki, Tsilidis, Ioannidis, Campbell and Theodoratou2017).

Statistics

The use of null hypothesis significance testing using standard significance thresholds (i.e., an alpha level of 0.05) has been repeatedly criticised (Wasserstein and Lazar, Reference Wasserstein and Lazar2016; Szucs and Ioannidis, Reference Szucs and Ioannidis2017). As a temporising measure, recently a proposal has been made to lower significance p-value threshold to 0.005 (Ioannidis, Reference Ioannidis2018). Such a threshold may ultimately aid in the identification of more robust (i.e., ‘true’) findings and the dropping of less consistent and less reproducible results, which may possibly contribute to the design of more methodologically sound studies in the future. Meta-analyses and umbrella reviews may also apply such thresholds to previously published evidence from RCTs. Pooling data from several RCTs may overcome the lack of power to reach this more stringent significance levels of p < 0.005 for harmful outcomes. For evidence derived from observational studies, even 0.005 is likely to be a lenient threshold. There is a lack of consensus on what might be an optimal threshold (or even whether a threshold should be used), but several previous umbrella reviews have used an even stricter level of p < 10−6. Another approach is to consider falsification endpoints to adjust the p-value threshold to the peculiarities of different fields (Prasad and Jena, Reference Prasad and Jena2013). In this approach, p-value thresholds are tailored to the specific research setting and even to a specific database.

Several other parameters should be accounted for when assessing the evidence from meta-analyses of observational studies and of RCTs. First, publication bias and selective reporting biases may be particularly influential. There is no statistical test with high sensitivity and specificity to assess these biases and the literature is replete of misleading claims where such tests are misused and misinterpreted (Lau et al., Reference Lau, Ioannidis, Terrin, Schmid and Olkin2006; Sterne et al., Reference Sterne, Sutton, Ioannidis, Terrin, Jones, Lau, Carpenter, Rucker, Harbord, Schmid, Tetzlaff, Deeks, Peters, Macaskill, Schwarzer, Duval, Altman, Moher and Higgins2011). It is probably reasonable to use a combination of tests, such as a small-study effects test (Egger et al., Reference Egger, Davey Smith, Schneider and Minder1997) that evaluates whether small studies could bias (i.e., inflate) the summary effect size of a meta-analytic estimate and an excess of significance test that may evaluate whether there is an excess of observed significant (i.e., ‘positive’) findings in relation to expected ones (Ioannidis and Trikalinos, Reference Ioannidis and Trikalinos2007). One may also assess whether the largest study could provide a more conservative estimate than the summary effect size (Belbasis et al., Reference Belbasis, Bellou and Evangelou2016). Furthermore, statistical measures of heterogeneity can be assessed, e.g., with I 2 >50% indicating large heterogeneity. However, often I 2 estimates are not precise (i.e., confidence intervals are large) (Ioannidis et al., Reference Ioannidis, Patsopoulos and Evangelou2007) and statistical heterogeneity is only modestly correlated with biological and/or clinical heterogeneity. For adverse events that are uncommon, the power to detect heterogeneity between studies may be very low. Prediction intervals should also be routinely presented in meta-analyses (IntHout et al., Reference IntHout, Ioannidis, Rovers and Goeman2016), as they also accommodate the impact of between-study heterogeneity. Finally, the magnitude of the effect size should be taken into account when moving from methodological to clinical considerations of relevance and impact.

Quality of single studies and meta-analyses

There is a factory of tools that aim to assess ‘quality’ of studies. None of them is perfect and quality assessments based on reported features may not reflect what actually happened during the conduct of a study (Ioannidis and Lau, Reference Ioannidis and Lau1998). Considering these caveats, quality of observational studies (both case-control and cohort studies) can be evaluated with tools, such as the New-Castle Ottawa Scale (Wells et al., Reference Wells, Shea, O'Connell, Peterson, Welch, Losos and Tugwell2013). For RCTs, even the term ‘quality’ has fallen (justifiably) into disfavour and ‘risk of bias assessment’ is considered more appropriate, e.g., as can be conducted with the Cochrane Risk of Bias tool (Schünemann et al., Reference Schünemann, Brożek, Guyatt and Oxman2013).

For systematic reviews, Assessing the Methodological Quality of Systematic Reviews (AMSTAR) (Shea et al., Reference Shea, Hamel, Wells, Bouter, Kristjansson, Grimshaw, Henry and Boers2009; Pollock et al., Reference Pollock, Fernandes and Hartling2017) is the most popular tool to assesses the methodological ‘quality’ of a systematic review and meta-analysis (both observational and interventional). However, quality is almost as intangible (or more) for meta-analyses, as it is for single trials. It has been pointed out that AMSTAR scoring relies more on the ‘reporting’ quality, rather than ‘methodological’ quality (Pollock et al., Reference Pollock, Fernandes and Hartling2017). Also, AMSTAR completely neglects the single studies’ design, pooled effect size, or sample size. Several attempts have been made to enhance AMSTAR from a mere ‘methodological’ scoring to a ‘clinically meaningful’ assessment. For example, AMSTAR-2 (Shea et al., Reference Shea, Reeves, Wells, Thuku, Hamel, Moran, Moher, Tugwell, Welch, Kristjansson and Henry2017) has introduced more items, accounting for the presence of randomisation or not in the interventional studies. Second, AMSTAR-plus (Correll et al., Reference Correll, Rubio, Inczedy-Farkas, Birnbaum, Kane and Leucht2017) in addition to study design, accounts for sample size, effect size and presence (not only assessment) of publication bias. Again, additional caveats exist, e.g., our poor ability to judge the presence of publication bias based on reported data. Moreover, the newer versions of AMSTAR do not apply to meta-analyses of observational studies.

Reproducibility and transparency

Lack of reproducibility and transparency is a major issue that should be addressed by researchers themselves and journal editors in primis. Unfortunately, until now, in the vast majority of studies, the raw data or even the protocols for them were not available in public (Iqbal et al., Reference Iqbal, Wallach, Khoury, Schully and Ioannidis2016). However, this is hopefully going to change in the future (Munafò et al., Reference Munafò, Nosek, Bishop, Button, Chambers, Percie du Sert, Simonsohn, Wagenmakers, Ware and Ioannidis2017). Therefore, assessing whether raw data and protocols are available for independent re-analyses may be another dimension to consider in assessing the validity and credibility of evidence. Published re-analyses in the past have shown many major differences v. the original publications (Ebrahim et al., Reference Ebrahim, Sohani, Montoya, Agarwal, Thorlund, Mills and Ioannidis2014), but this may become less of a common problem once transparency and sharing become the norm (Naudet et al., Reference Naudet, Sakarovitch, Janiaud, Cristea, Fanelli, Moher and Ioannidis2018). When computational components are involved, sharing of computer codes helps transparency (Stodden et al., Reference Stodden, McNutt, Bailey, Deelman, Gil, Hanson, Heroux, Ioannidis and Taufer2016).

Moving from quality assessment, grading of credibility, to making recommendations

A certain degree of overlap can be found between credibility and certainty assessment across different existing frameworks. For example, according to AMSTAR-2 (Shea et al., Reference Shea, Reeves, Wells, Thuku, Hamel, Moran, Moher, Tugwell, Welch, Kristjansson and Henry2017) or AMSTAR-plus (Correll et al., Reference Correll, Rubio, Inczedy-Farkas, Birnbaum, Kane and Leucht2017), randomisation is a higher quality criterion. On the other hand, GRADE (Schünemann et al., Reference Schünemann, Brożek, Guyatt and Oxman2013) handbook retains randomisation or blinding design of RCTs as criteria that contribute to higher certainty as opposed to observational designs. Other differences can be found across grading systems. GRADE (Schünemann et al., Reference Schünemann, Brożek, Guyatt and Oxman2013) accounts also for effect size magnitude in estimating certainty of evidence, while other frameworks do not include this component in the panel of criteria to grade credibility of evidence (Bellou et al., Reference Bellou, Belbasis, Tzoulaki, Evangelou and Ioannidis2016). Also, while credibility grading frameworks from Ioannidis (Belbasis et al., Reference Belbasis, Bellou and Evangelou2016) differentiate the grading of evidence from observational studies and RCTs (Theodoratou et al., Reference Theodoratou, Tzoulaki, Zgaga and Ioannidis2014; Li et al., Reference Li, Meng, Timofeeva, Tzoulaki, Tsilidis, Ioannidis, Campbell and Theodoratou2017) applying different thresholds of aforementioned features, GRADE (Schünemann et al., Reference Schünemann, Brożek, Guyatt and Oxman2013) accounts upgrades or downgrades of evidence certainty within the same framework considering both observational and randomised trial data.

Beyond quality and credibility and (un)certainty assessment, when it comes to making recommendations, additional features need to be taken into account. First of all, the clinical relevance of any finding must be considered and this has little to do with the level of statistical significance. Small effect sizes or poor relevance of outcomes of interest may preclude any recommendation, even when it seems to be based on high quality and highly statistically significant findings. Also, recommendations should always account for benefit/risk ratio. For example, a medication that is slightly more effective than an already available medication, which has a much higher frequency of severe harms, cannot really be recommended. Also, the economic evaluation of resource allocation in relation to the socio-economic burden of the disease has to be accounted for by the main stakeholders involved.

From feasibility to perfection: what is the trade-off?

Assessment of evidence on harms of psychopharmacologic medications from observational studies or RCTs should consider the assessment of multiple aspects, including research design, statistical features, quality of single studies and meta-analyses and the reproducibility and transparency of the evidence.

The full-assessment of the comprehensive list of features mentioned in this editorial may require an in-depth assessment of the published literature and, when some information is not available in the original published articles, it could be necessary to contact authors to ask further data. The extent to which unavailable information can be retrieved can vary a lot, though. Moreover, the resources needed to ‘clean’ the published literature after the fact may be enormous and perfect ‘cleaning’ may be a utopian endeavour. In-depth efforts may need to be prioritised for effects and associations that are likely to be influential, i.e., graded highly or considered to have clinical portend. In-depth looks at the data may reveal errors that render the conclusions invalid, but often the necessary additional data for such in-depth assessments and re-analyses will not be available and might be impossible to obtain. Recording of harms can be erratic and efforts at harm attribution may add extra levels of bias. Overall, it is important to use resources wisely and try to conclude objectively whether the evidence is worth trusting and to what degree. Regardless, a systematic approach is necessary to replace narrative arbitrary reviews, or reviews of reviews without systematic approaches that can be highly subjective and thus unreliable. It is hoped that the concepts covered in this editorial and summarised in Table 1 can provide a reporting and evaluation framework that can guide research and, ultimately, enhance the quality, accuracy and robustness of research findings.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Conflict of interest

None for MS, AFC and JPAI. CUC has has been a consultant and/or advisor to or has received honoraria from: Alkermes, Allergan, Angelini, Gerson Lehrman Group, IntraCellular Therapies, Janssen/J&J, LB Pharma, Lundbeck, Medavante, Medscape, Merck, Neurocrine, Otsuka, Pfizer, ROVI, Servier, Sunovion, Takeda, and Teva. He has provided expert testimony for Bristol-Myers Squibb, Janssen and Otsuka. He served on a Data Safety Monitoring Board for Lundbeck, ROVI and Teva. He received royalties from UpToDate and grant support from Janssen and Takeda. He is also a shareholder of LB Pharma.

References

American Psychiatric Association (2013) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 5th Edn. Washington, DC: Author.Google Scholar
Belbasis, L, Bellou, V and Evangelou, E (2016) Environmental risk factors and amyotrophic lateral sclerosis: an Umbrella review and critical assessment of current evidence from systematic reviews and meta-analyses of observational studies. Neuroepidemiology 46, 96105.Google Scholar
Bellou, V, Belbasis, L, Tzoulaki, I, Evangelou, E and Ioannidis, JP (2016) Environmental risk factors and Parkinson's disease: an umbrella review of meta-analyses. Parkinsonism Related Disorders 23, 19.Google Scholar
Cipriani, A, Furukawa, TA, Salanti, G, Chaimani, A, Atkinson, LZ, Ogawa, Y, Leucht, S, Ruhe, HG, Turner, EH, Higgins, JPT, Egger, M, Takeshima, N, Hayasaka, Y, Imai, H, Shinohara, K, Tajika, A, Ioannidis, JPA and Geddes, JR (2018) Comparative efficacy and acceptability of 21 antidepressant drugs for the acute treatment of adults with major depressive disorder: a systematic review and network meta-analysis. Lancet 391, 13571366.Google Scholar
Cohen, J (1988) Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences. (Ed. Routledge). ISBN 1-134-74270-3.Google Scholar
Correll, CU, Rubio, JM, Inczedy-Farkas, G, Birnbaum, ML, Kane, JM and Leucht, S (2017) Efficacy of 42 pharmacologic cotreatment strategies added to antipsychotic monotherapy in schizophrenia: systematic overview and quality appraisal of the meta-analytic evidence. Journal of American Medical Association Psychiatry 74, 675684.Google Scholar
Ebrahim, S, Sohani, ZN, Montoya, L, Agarwal, A, Thorlund, K, Mills, EJ and Ioannidis, JP (2014) Reanalyses of randomized clinical trial data. Journal of America Medical Association 312, 10241032.Google Scholar
Egger, M, Davey Smith, G, Schneider, M and Minder, C (1997) Bias in meta-analysis detected by a simple, graphical test. British Medical Journal 315, 629634.Google Scholar
Higgins, JP and Thompson, SG (2002) Quantifying heterogeneity in a meta-analysis. Statistics in Medicine 21, 15391558.Google Scholar
IntHout, J, Ioannidis, JP, Rovers, MM and Goeman, JJ (2016) Plea for routinely presenting prediction intervals in meta-analysis. British Medical Journal Open 6, e010247.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP (2009 a) Adverse events in randomized trials: neglected, restricted, distorted, and silenced. Archives of Internal Medicine 169, 17371739.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP (2009 b) Integration of evidence from multiple meta-analyses: a primer on umbrella reviews, treatment networks and multiple treatments meta-analyses. Canadian Medical Association Journal 181, 488493.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP (2016) The mass production of redundant, misleading, and conflicted systematic reviews and meta-analyses. The Milbank Quarterly 94, 485514.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, J (2017) Next-generation systematic reviews: prospective meta-analysis, individual-level data, networks and umbrella reviews. British Journal of Sports Medicine 51, 14561458.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JPA (2018) The proposal to lower p value thresholds to .005. Journal of American Medical Association 319, 14291430.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP and Lau, J (1998) Can quality of clinical trials and meta-analyses be quantified? Lancet 352, 590591.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP and Trikalinos, TA (2007) An exploratory test for an excess of significant findings. Clinical Trials 4, 245253..Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP, Evans, SJ, Gotzsche, PC, O'Neill, RT, Altman, DG, Schulz, K, Moher, D and Group, C (2004) Better reporting of harms in randomized trials: an extension of the CONSORT statement. Annals of Internal Medicine 141, 781788.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, JP, Patsopoulos, NA and Evangelou, E (2007) Uncertainty in heterogeneity estimates in meta-analyses. British Medical Journal 335, 914916.Google Scholar
Iqbal, SA, Wallach, JD, Khoury, MJ, Schully, SD and Ioannidis, JP (2016) Reproducible research practices and transparency across the biomedical literature. PLoS Biology 14, e1002333.Google Scholar
Lau, J, Ioannidis, JP, Terrin, N, Schmid, CH and Olkin, I (2006) The case of the misleading funnel plot. British Medical Journal 333, 597600.Google Scholar
Leucht, S, Cipriani, A, Spineli, L, Mavridis, D, Orey, D, Richter, F, Samara, M, Barbui, C, Engel, RR, Geddes, JR, Kissling, W, Stapf, MP, Lassig, B, Salanti, G and Davis, JM (2013) Comparative efficacy and tolerability of 15 antipsychotic drugs in schizophrenia: a multiple-treatments meta-analysis. Lancet 382, 951962.Google Scholar
Li, X, Meng, X, Timofeeva, M, Tzoulaki, I, Tsilidis, KK, Ioannidis, JP, Campbell, H and Theodoratou, E (2017) Serum uric acid levels and multiple health outcomes: umbrella review of evidence from observational studies, randomised controlled trials, and Mendelian randomisation studies. British Medical Journal 357, j2376.Google Scholar
Munafò, MR, Nosek, BA, Bishop, DVM, Button, KS, Chambers, CD, Percie du Sert, N, Simonsohn, U, Wagenmakers, E-J, Ware, JJ and Ioannidis, JPA (2017) A manifesto for reproducible science. Nature Human Behaviour 1, 0021.Google Scholar
Naudet, F, Sakarovitch, C, Janiaud, P, Cristea, I, Fanelli, D, Moher, D and Ioannidis, JPA (2018) Data sharing and reanalysis of randomized controlled trials in leading biomedical journals with a full data sharing policy: survey of studies published in The BMJ and PLOS medicine. British Medical Journal 360, k400.Google Scholar
Papanikolaou, PN and Ioannidis, JP (2004) Availability of large-scale evidence on specific harms from systematic reviews of randomized trials. American Journal of Medicine 117, 582589.Google Scholar
Papanikolaou, PN, Christidi, GD and Ioannidis, JP (2006) Comparison of evidence on harms of medical interventions in randomized and nonrandomized studies. Canadian Medical Association Journal 174, 635641.Google Scholar
Pollock, M, Fernandes, RM and Hartling, L (2017) Evaluation of AMSTAR to assess the methodological quality of systematic reviews in overviews of reviews of healthcare interventions. BioMed Central Medical Research Methodology 17, 48.Google Scholar
Prasad, V and Jena, AB (2013) Prespecified falsification end points: can they validate true observational associations? Journal of American Medical Association 309, 241242.Google Scholar
Sawilowsky, S (2009) New effect size rules of thumb. Journal of Modern Applied Statistical Methods 8, 467474.Google Scholar
Schünemann, H, Brożek, J, Guyatt, G and Oxman, A (2013) Handbook for grading the quality of evidence and the strength of recommendations using the GRADE approach. Available at http://gdt.guidelinedevelopment.org/app/handbook/handbook.html (Accessed 31 May 2018).Google Scholar
Shea, BJ, Hamel, C, Wells, GA, Bouter, LM, Kristjansson, E, Grimshaw, J, Henry, DA and Boers, M (2009) AMSTAR is a reliable and valid measurement tool to assess the methodological quality of systematic reviews. Journal of Clinical Epidemiol 62, 10131020.Google Scholar
Shea, BJ, Reeves, BC, Wells, G, Thuku, M, Hamel, C, Moran, J, Moher, D, Tugwell, P, Welch, V, Kristjansson, E and Henry, DA (2017) AMSTAR 2: a critical appraisal tool for systematic reviews that include randomised or non-randomised studies of healthcare interventions, or both. British Medical Journal 358, j4008.Google Scholar
Solmi, M, Murru, A, Pacchiarotti, I, Undurraga, J, Veronese, N, Fornaro, M, Stubbs, B, Monaco, F, Vieta, E, Seeman, MV, Correll, CU and Carvalho, AF (2017) Safety, tolerability, and risks associated with first- and second-generation antipsychotics: a state-of-the-art clinical review. Therapeutics and clinical risk management. 13, 757777.Google Scholar
Sterne, JA, Sutton, AJ, Ioannidis, JP, Terrin, N, Jones, DR, Lau, J, Carpenter, J, Rucker, G, Harbord, RM, Schmid, CH, Tetzlaff, J, Deeks, JJ, Peters, J, Macaskill, P, Schwarzer, G, Duval, S, Altman, DG, Moher, D and Higgins, JP (2011) Recommendations for examining and interpreting funnel plot asymmetry in meta-analyses of randomised controlled trials. British Medical Journal 343, d4002.Google Scholar
Stodden, V, McNutt, M, Bailey, DH, Deelman, E, Gil, Y, Hanson, B, Heroux, MA, Ioannidis, JP and Taufer, M (2016) Enhancing reproducibility for computational methods. Science 354, 12401241.Google Scholar
Szucs, D and Ioannidis, JPA (2017) When null hypothesis significance testing is unsuitable for research: a reassessment. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11, 390.Google Scholar
Theodoratou, E, Tzoulaki, I, Zgaga, L and Ioannidis, JP (2014) Vitamin D and multiple health outcomes: umbrella review of systematic reviews and meta-analyses of observational studies and randomised trials. British Medical Journal 348, g2035.Google Scholar
Veronese, N, Solmi, M, Caruso, MG, Giannelli, G, Osella, AR, Evangelou, E, Maggi, S, Fontana, L, Stubbs, B and Tzoulaki, I (2018) Dietary fiber and health outcomes: an umbrella review of systematic reviews and meta-analyses. American Journal of Clinical Nutrition 107, 436444.Google Scholar
Wasserstein, RL and Lazar, NA (2016) The ASA's statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose. The American Statistician 70, 129133.Google Scholar
Weihrauch, TR and Gauler, TC (1999) Placebo-efficacy and adverse effects in controlled clinical trials. Arzneimittel-Forschung 49, 385393.Google Scholar
Wells, G, Shea, B, O'Connell, D, Peterson, J, Welch, V, Losos, M and Tugwell, P (2013) The Newcastle-Ottawa Scale (NOS) for assessing the quality of nonrandomised studies in meta-analyses. Available at http://www.ohri.ca/programs/clinical_epidemiology/oxford.asp (Accessed 31 May 2018).Google Scholar
Zorzela, L, Loke, YK, Ioannidis, JP, Golder, S, Santaguida, P, Altman, DG, Moher, D, Vohra, S and Group, PR (2016) PRISMA harms checklist: improving harms reporting in systematic reviews. British Medical Journal 352, i157.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Factors that may be considered in the assessment of the evidence on harms outcomes of pharmacological interventions from meta-analyses of observational or interventional studies