Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
  • Cited by 15
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Online publication date:
July 2011
Print publication year:
2011
Online ISBN:
9780511977206

Book description

Philosophers have long been concerned about what we know and how we know it. Increasingly, however, a related question has gained prominence in philosophical discussion: what should we believe and why? This volume brings together twelve new essays that address different aspects of this question. The essays examine foundational questions about reasons for belief, and use new research on reasons for belief to address traditional epistemological concerns such as knowledge, justification and perceptually acquired beliefs. This book will be of interest to philosophers working on epistemology, theoretical reason, rationality, perception and ethics. It will also be of interest to cognitive scientists and psychologists who wish to gain deeper insight into normative questions about belief and knowledge.

Reviews

"This book focuses on what are called theoretical reasons. The topic of interest resides both in practical philosophy, where the importance of the ability to give reasons for action has long been recognized, and in several specific areas of epistemology, where reasons play important roles in regard to questions of justification, warrant, and epistemic entitlement.... Recommended.... Upper-level undergraduates through researchers/faculty."
--N.D. Smith, Lewis and Clark College, Choice

Refine List

Actions for selected content:

Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Contents

  • 1 - How to be a teleologist about epistemic reasons
    pp 13-33
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter explores the prospects of a slightly different strategy in solving the value problem for the teleological account of epistemic reasons. The starting point of the strategy is to concede the main criticism of teleological accounts of epistemic reasons, namely that epistemic properties are not valuable generally and in all contexts, and that a teleological account relying on such a claim therefore fails. The notion of reasons to form beliefs about propositions or subject matters is in some respects similar to the notion of having a reason to engage in enquiry, i.e. a reason to actively pursue evidence bearing on a certain proposition or subject matter. The chapter argues that the relationship between epistemic reasons, reasons to form beliefs about certain propositions, and normative statements about what a person ought to believe, could be explained by supposing that epistemic reasons are hypothetical instrumental reasons.
  • 2 - Is there reason to be theoretically rational?
    pp 34-53
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter focuses at the more specific matter of whether there is reason to be theoretically rational. It argues that there is very strong reason to be theoretically rational. Unfortunately, answering the question about theoretical rationality does not settle questions about the normativity of practical rationality, but the chapter outlines in a speculative way how the considerations raised in favor of the normativity of theoretical rationality might be used to show that the requirements of practical rationality are normative. The use of wide-scope oughts, or perhaps wide-scope reasons, in giving an account of rational requirements is important for any view that holds that rational requirements are normative. The initial error is in thinking that rational requirements are conceptually identical to normative requirements. The truth of the particular normative requirement is, like any other ought, determined by the various features of the world on which normativity is dependent.
  • 3 - Epistemic motivation
    pp 54-74
  • Towards a metaethics of belief
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter sets the programme for building up a metaethics of belief from the unexplored angle of motivation. It introduces and transposes to epistemology three standard metaethical debates, internalism versus externalism about the connection between moral judgements and motivation; Humeanism versus anti-Humeanism about the nature of motivation; and cognitivism versus non-cognitivism about moral judgements. The chapter shows how the position on motivation affects the commitments in the higher, more metaphysical, realms of our metaethics of belief: in particular, it makes cognitivism about epistemic judgements prima facie plausible. It shows that loftier metaethical questions can be answered from a stance on motivation. As far as motivation goes, then, our metaethics of belief should be anti-Humean about the nature of epistemic motivation, and internalist about how epistemic judgements motivate us. Methodologically, the kind in question is one which builds itself up from theoretically lower-level commitments concerning motivation.
  • 4 - Error theory and reasons for belief
    pp 75-93
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter outlines the alleged structural similarities between moral reasons and epistemic reasons and gives a more precise characterization of epistemic error theory. It distinguishes between transcendent norms, which imply categorical reasons, and immanent norms, which do not imply categorical reasons. The chapter explores the question of what error theorists should say about reasons for belief. It examines what Terence Cuneo claims to be three undesirable results of epistemic error theory, namely that epistemic error theory is self-defeating or polemically toothless, that epistemic error theory implies that there can be no arguments for anything, and that epistemic error theory rules out the possibility of epistemic merits and demerits. The chapter argues that for the purpose of distinguishing belief from other kinds of attitudes the norms involved in belief ascriptions need not be understood as transcendent rather than immanent and consequently there are no worrisome implications for epistemic error theory.
  • 5 - Can reasons for belief be debunked?
    pp 94-108
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Since the debate between evidentialists and pragmatists is not about the causes of belief, but instead about what normative standard to apply in determining what to believe, we have no choice but to accept the evidentialist standard. Whether one explicitly recognizes it or not, one is committed to evidentialism just in virtue of asking what to believe. Addressed to the error theorist, arguments favoring evidentialism over pragmatism merely beg the question. By attributing beliefs about doxastic reasons, the theorist about doxastic reasons commits himself to the falsity of his own view. Transcendental arguments seek to vindicate the objective validity of the fundamental normative judgments by bridging the gap between the first and third-personal points of view. As long as the results of Kantian arguments are confined to claims about what norms must be accepted from the first-personal point of view, error theories about those norms appear to be left open.
  • 6 - Reasons and belief's justification
    pp 111-130
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter looks at some competing accounts of reasons and their demands. Some object to the conformity and compliance accounts on the grounds that they represent reasons as making unreasonable demands. The considerations that cause trouble for the conformity and compliance accounts suggest that normative appraisal is concerned with both the quality and results of the deliberative efforts. The chapter argues that there's something wrong with two influential approaches to epistemic justification. It focuses on evidentialism and the knowledge account because they face structurally similar problems. There's more to a belief's justification than the evidentialist maintains and less to a belief's justification than the knowledge account says. The problem with the evidentialist view is that it restricts the scope of epistemic evaluation to relations between a belief and the evidence an individual happens to have on hand.
  • 7 - Perception, generality, and reasons
    pp 131-157
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter argues that perceptual experiences must have content if they are to rationalize beliefs, at least in the sense that has traditionally been invoked in the context of epistemological debates about empirical justification. The representational content, Bill Brewer thinks, is modeled on that of a person's thought about the world around him, as expressed in his linguistic communication with others, and registered by their everyday attitude ascriptions to him. A view of perception which apparently meets this need, while still remaining within the spirit of the object view, is defended by Mark Johnston, for whom perception presents with states and events as well as objects and stuffs. The modifications made to the object view do indeed entail that perception resembles thought in having representational content, and specifically representational content with the generality characteristic of the content of thought.
  • 8 - Immediate warrant, epistemic responsibility, and Moorean dogmatism
    pp 158-179
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Epistemologists and non-philosophers find the Moorean reasoning unattractive. It is not easy to locate the source of this dissatisfaction, however. This chapter argues that it arises from requirements of responsibility that apply to rational agents in the course of conscious reasoning or deliberation. Dogmatism alone isn't enough to evade standard arguments for skepticism about the external world. Warrants are things of a type that is suited to play the role of normative epistemic reasons in an agent's deliberations about what to believe. A person might have a warrant to believe a particular proposition, believe that proposition, and yet not hold that belief in a reasonable, epistemically appropriate, or epistemically satisfactory way. The external world skeptic holds that no one is doxastically justified in believing anything about the external world by means of the senses. The Moorean dogmatist diagnoses this skeptical claim as arising from a principle about experiential warrant.
  • 9 - Primitively rational belief-forming processes
    pp 180-200
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter focuses on belief-forming processes, that is, types of mental process that result in the thinker's forming a belief in some proposition. It discusses a specific example of the belief-forming process that has three properties. The chapter articulates some crucial features that all rational belief-forming processes must have, without attempting to ensure that these crucial features are picked out in strictly non-normative terms. It explains what it would mean for the rationality of a belief-forming process to be a priori. The chapter argues that the rationality of the primitively rational processes is a priori in this way. It argues that the mere existence of an essential connection between a belief-forming process and the truth was not enough to make the process rational; it is also necessary that one should be able to engage in this process precisely because of its connection with the truth.
  • 10 - What does it take to “have” a reason?
    pp 201-222
  • View abstract

    Summary

    The truism that adopting an unjustified belief does not put one in a better evidential position with respect to believing its consequences leads most philosophers to conclude that bare belief is insufficient for the having relation involved in subjective evidence. This chapter presents alternative explanation of PP, the truism that when a belief lacks propositional justification, it does not contribute to the propositional justification for its consequences. The assumption of a high bar on what it takes to have evidence, despite its overwhelming initial plausibility, has been complicating the dialectic about basic perceptual epistemology, and consequently the dialectic about foundationalism and coherentism, internalism and externalism, and rationalism and empiricism, for a very long time. Beliefs can be justified or unjustified because they fall under the reach of rational criticism, and they fall under the reach of rational criticism because they are states that we hold for reasons.
  • 11 - Knowledge and reasons for belief
    pp 223-243
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter seeks to make sense of the idea that, for agents, knowledge at least normally goes along with being justified in believing. It indicates how one might develop an account of testimony building on a non standard account of knowledge from indicator phenomena. A conception of the importance of recognitional abilities is developed to yield an account of reasons for belief in the cases under consideration and a general view of the connection between knowledge, justified belief and reasons. A problem structure analogous to that described in relation to testimony arises in cases of perceptual knowledge. By contrast with perceptual knowledge, the problem is not that what is thought to supply the reason is not of the right category to constitute a reason. The chapter explains how with respect to various kinds of knowledge one can gain a lot from what initially seemed to be so little.
  • 12 - What is the swamping problem?
    pp 244-259
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter discusses the constitutive relationship between belief and truth. This relationship is expressed in terms of the slogan that belief in some sense 'aims' at the truth; that the telos of belief is truth. The standard way of expressing the swamping problem is as posing a difficulty not for a general epistemological thesis like epistemic value T-monism but rather for particular epistemological proposals, such as reliabilism. The epistemic value conferred on a belief by that belief having an epistemic property is instrumental epistemic value relative to the further epistemic good of true belief. It is important to note that the problem that Plato expressed is different to the problem posed by the swamping problem. With epistemic value K-monism in play, however, the question of why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief has a straightforward answer: because knowledge, unlike true belief, is a fundamental epistemic value.
References
Adler, J. 2002. Belief's Own Ethics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Alston, W. 1988. The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 257–299.
Alston, W. 2005. Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Armstrong, D. 1973. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.
Audi, R. 1997. Moral Judgment and Reasons for Action. In Ethics and Practical Reason (ed. Cullity, G. and Gaut, B.). Cambridge University Press, 125–160.
Audi, R. 2001. An Internalist Theory of Normative Grounds. Philosophical Topics 29: 19–46.
Bealer, G. 2000. A Theory of the A Priori. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81: 1–30.
Bird, A. 2007. Justified Judging. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 81–110.
Blackburn, S. 1998. Ruling Passions. New York: Oxford University Press.
Boghossian, P. 2002. How Are Objective Epistemic Reasons Possible? In Reason and Nature: Essays in the Theory of Rationality (ed. Bermúdez, J. L. and Millar, A.). Oxford University Press, 15–48.
Boghossian, P.. 2003a. Blind Reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 77: 225–248.
Boghossian, P.. 2003b. The Normativity of Content. Philosophical Issues 13: 31–45.
BonJour, L. 1980. Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5: 53–74.
BonJour, L.. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brady, M. S. and Pritchard, D. H. (eds.) 2003. Moral and Epistemic Virtues. Oxford: Blackwell.
Bratman, M. 1999. Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason. Chicago: CSLI Publications.
Brewer, B. 1999. Perception and Reason. Oxford University Press.
Brewer, B.. 2004. Realism and the Nature of Perceptual Experience. Philosophical Issues 14: 61–77.
Brewer, B.. 2006. Perception and Content. European Journal of Philosophy 14(2): 165–181.
Brewer, B.. 2008. How to Account for Illusion. In Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge (ed. Haddock, A. and Macpherson, F.). Oxford University Press, 168–180.
Brogaard, B. 2005. I Know. Therefore, I Understand (MS).
Brogaard, B.. 2006. Can Virtue Reliabilism Explain the Value of Knowledge? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 335–354.
Broome, J. 2000. Normative Requirements. Ratio 12: 398–419.
Broome, J.. 2001. Normative Practical Reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 75: 175–193.
Broome, J.. 2004. Reasons. In Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (ed. Wallace, R. J., Pettit, P., Scheffler, S., and Smith, M.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 28–55.
Broome, J.. 2005. Does Rationality Give Us Reasons? Philosophical Issues 15: 321–337.
Broome, J.. 2007a. Does Rationality Consist in Correctly Responding to Reasons? Journal of Moral Philosophy 4: 349–374.
Broome, J. 2007b. Is Rationality Normative? Disputatio 27: 161–178.
Broome, J.. 2007c. Wide or Narrow Scope? Mind 116: 359–370.
Burge, T. 1993. Content Preservation. Philosophical Review 102: 457–488.
Broome, J. 2003. Perceptual Entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67: 503–548.
Bykvist, K. and Hattiangadi, A. 2007. Does Thought Imply Ought? Analysis 67: 277–285.
Byrne, A. 2005. Perception and Conceptual Content. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (ed. Steup, M. and Sosa, E.). Oxford: Blackwell, 231–250.
Campbell, J. 2002. Reference and Consciousness. Oxford University Press.
Cassam, Q. 2007. Ways of Knowing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107: 339–358.
Chen, C. 2006. Empirical Content and Rational Constraint. Inquiry 49(3): 242–264.
Child, W. 1994. Causality, Interpretation and the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Chisholm, R. 1957. Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Coady, C. A. J. 1992. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cohen, S. 1984. Justification and Truth. Philosophical Studies 46: 279–295.
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. 2001. Internalism Defended. American Philosophical Quarterly 38: 1–18.
Conee, E., Feldman, R. 2004. Evidentialism. Oxford University Press.
Cottingham, J. 2002. Descartes and the Voluntariness of Belief. The Monist 85(3): 343–360.
Cullity, G. and Gaut, B. (eds.) 1997. Ethics and Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cuneo, T. 2007. The Normative Web. Oxford University Press.
Dancy, J. 1993. Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.
Dancy, J.. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.
Dancy, J.. 2004. Enticing Reasons. In Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (ed. Wallace, R. J., Pettit, P., Scheffler, S., and Smith, M.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 91–118.
Danielsson, S. and Olson, J. 2007. Brentano and the Buck-Passers. Mind 116: 511–522.
David, M. 2001. Truth as the Epistemic Goal. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Virtue, and Responsibility (ed. Steup, M.). Oxford University Press, 151–169.
David, M.. 2005. Truth as the Primary Epistemic Goal: A Working Hypothesis. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (ed. M. Steup and E. Sosa). Oxford: Blackwell, 296–312.
Davidson, D. 1983. A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge. In Kant oder Hegel (ed. Henrich, D.). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Reprinted in Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (ed. E. LePore). Oxford: Blackwell, 307–319.
Dreier, J. 2002. The Expressivist Circle: Invoking Norms in the Explanation of Normative Judgement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 136–143.
Dretske, F. 1969. Seeing and Knowing. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Dretske, F.. 1970. Epistemic Operators. Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023. Reprinted in Dretske, 2000: 30–47.
Dretske, F.. 1971. Conclusive Reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1–22. Reprinted in Dretske, 2000: 3–29.
Dretske, F.. 2000. Perception, Knowledge and Belief: Selected Essays. Cambridge University Press.
Elgin, C. 2009. Is Understanding Factive? In Epistemic Value (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H.). Oxford University Press, 322–330.
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. 2002. Evidence, Pragmatics, and Justification. Philosophical Review 111: 67–94.
Feldman, R. 1988a. Epistemic Obligations. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 235–256.
Feldman, R. 1988b. Having Evidence. Reprinted in Evidentialism (E. Conee and R. Feldman). Oxford University Press, 2004, 219–241.
Feldman, R.. 1988c. Subjective and Objective Justification in Ethics and Epistemology. The Monist 71: 405–419.
Finlay, S. 2008. The Error in the Error Theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86: 347–369.
Fletcher, G. 2009. Uneasy Companions. Ratio 22: 359–368.
Foley, R. 1987. The Theory of Epistemic Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Foot, P. 1972. Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives. Philosophical Review 91: 305–317.
Fricker, M. 2003. Epistemic Justice and a Role for Virtue in the Politics of Knowing. Metaphilosophy 34: 154–173.
Fumerton, R. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MA: Rowman and Littlefield.
Fumerton, R.. 2006. The Epistemic Role of Testimony: Internalist and Externalist Perspectives. In The Epistemology of Testimony (ed. Lackey, J. and Sosa, E.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 77–92.
Gardner, J. 2005. Wrongs and Faults. The Review of Metaphysics 59: 95–132.
Gardner, J.. 2007. Offences and Defences. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gettier, E. 1963. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis 23: 121–123.
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gibbons, J. Forthcoming. Things That Make Things Reasonable. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
Ginsborg, H. 2006a. Aesthetic Judgment and Perceptual Normativity. Inquiry 49(5): 403–437.
Ginsborg, H.. 2006b. Empirical Concepts and the Content of Experience. European Journal of Philosophy 14(3): 349–372.
Ginsborg, H. 2006c. Reasons for Belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72(2): 286–318.
Ginsborg, H.. Forthcoming. Primitive Normativity and Skepticism about Rules. Journal of Philosophy.
Gluer, K. and Wikforss, Å. 2009. Against Content Normativity. Mind 118: 31–70.
Goldman, A. 1976. Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge. Journal of Philosophy 73: 771–791.
Goldman, A. 1979. What is Justified Belief? In Justification and Knowledge (ed. Pappas, George). Dordrecht: Reidel, 1–23.
Goldman, A.. 1999a. Internalism Exposed. Journal of Philosophy 96: 271–293.
Goldman, A. 1999b. Knowledge in a Social World. New York: Oxford University Press.
Greco, J. 2002. Knowledge as Credit for True Belief. In Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (ed. DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L.). Oxford University Press, 111–134.
Greco, J.. 2007. The Nature of Ability and the Purpose of Knowledge. Philosophical Issues 17: 57–69.
Greco, J.. 2008. What's Wrong With Contextualism? Philosophical Quarterly 58: 416–436.
Greco, J.. 2009. The Value Problem. In Epistemic Value (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H.). Oxford University Press, 313–321.
Grimm, S. 2006. Is Understanding a Species of Knowledge? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 515–536.
Grimm, S.. 2009. Epistemic Normativity. In Epistemic Value (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H.). Oxford University Press, 243–264.
Gupta, A. 2006. Experience and Knowledge. In Perceptual Experience (ed. Gendler, T. S. and Hawthorne, J.). Oxford University Press, 181–204.
Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H. 2010. The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations. Oxford University Press.
Hampton, J. 1998. The Authority of Reason. Cambridge University Press.
Harman, G. 1990. The Intrinsic Quality of Experience. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 31–52.
Harman, G. 1999. Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind. Oxford University Press.
Hattiangadi, A. 2007. Oughts and Thoughts. Oxford University Press.
Hawthorne, J. and Stanley, J. 2008. Knowledge and Action. Journal of Philosophy, 105: 571–590.
Heathwood, C. 2009. Moral and Epistemic Open Question Arguments. Philosophical Books 50: 83–98.
Heck, R. 2000. Nonconceptual Content and the “Space of Reasons.” Philosophical Review 109(4): 483–523.
Herman, B. 1994. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hieronymi, P. 2005. The Wrong Kind of Reasons. Journal of Philosophy 102: 37–57.
Hieronymi, P.. 2009. Two Kinds of Agency. In Mental Actions (ed. L. O'Brien, and M. Soteriou, ). Oxford University Press, 138–162.
Horder, J. 2004. Excusing Crime. New York: Oxford University Press.
Huemer, M. 2007. Moore's Paradox and the Norm of Belief. In Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics (ed. Nuccetelli, S. and Seay, G.). New York: Oxford University Press, 142–157.
Husak, D. 1999. Conflicts of Justification. Law and Philosophy 18: 41–68.
Jackson, F. 1999. Non-Cognitivism, Normativity, Belief. Ratio 12(4): 420–435.
Johnston, M. 2006. Better than Mere Knowledge? The Function of Sensory Awareness. In Perceptual Experience (ed. Gendler, T. S. and Hawthorne, J.). Oxford University Press, 260–290.
Jones, W. 1997. Why Do We Value Knowledge? American Philosophical Quarterly 34: 423–440.
Joyce, R. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge University Press.
Joyce, R.. Forthcoming. The Error in “The Error in the Error Theory.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
Kant, I. 1787. Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 2nd (B) edition. Riga: Hartknoch.
Karlander, K. 2008. The Normativity of Thought and Meaning. Doctoral dissertation. Stockholm University.
Kasser, J. and Shah, N. 2006. The Metaethics of Belief: An Expressivist Reading of “The Will to Believe.” Social Epistemology 20(1): 1–17.
Kavka, G. 1983. The Toxin Puzzle. Analysis 43: 33–36.
Kelly, T. 2003. Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 612–640.
Kelly, T.. 2006. Evidence. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ed. Zalta, E. N.). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/evidence/#EviGuiTruEviSigSymMar
Kelly, T. 2007. Evidence and Normativity: Reply to Leite. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75: 465–474.
Kim, J. 1988. What is Naturalized Epistemology? Philosophical Perspectives 2: 381–405.
Kolodny, N. 2005. Why Be Rational? Mind 114(455): 509–563.
Kolodny, N.. 2007. State or Process Requirements? Mind 116(462): 371–385.
Kornblith, H. 1993. Epistemic Normativity. Synthese 94: 357–378.
Kvanvig, J. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kvanvig, J.. 2005. Truth is Not the Primary Epistemic Goal. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (ed. Steup, M. and Sosa, E.). Oxford: Blackwell, 285–296.
Kvanvig, J.. 2009a. Responses to Critics. In Epistemic Value (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H.). Oxford University Press, 339–351.
Kvanvig, J.. 2009b. The Value of Understanding. In Epistemic Value (ed. A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D. H. Pritchard). Oxford University Press, 95–111.
Lackey, J. 2007. The Norms of Assertion. Noûs 41: 594–626.
Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.) 2006. The Epistemology of Testimony. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Langsam, H. 2008. Rationality, Justification, and the Internalism/Externalism Debate. Erkenntnis 68: 79–101.
Lehrer, K. 1990. Theory of Knowledge. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Lehrer, K. and Paxson, T. 1969. Knowledge: Undefeated Justified True Belief. Journal of Philosophy 66(4): 225–237.
Leite, A. 2005. A Localist Solution to the Regress of Epistemic Justification. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 395–421.
Leite, A. 2007. Epistemic Instrumentalism and Reasons for Belief: A Reply to Tom Kelly's “Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique.”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75: 456–464.
Leite, A.. 2008. Believing One's Reasons Are Good. Synthese 161(3): 419–441.
Lewis, C. I. 1946. An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
Lillehammer, H. 2007. Companions in Guilt. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Littlejohn, C. The Myth of the False, Justified Belief (MS).
Littlejohn, C. 2009a. The Externalist's Demon. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39: 399–435.
Littlejohn, C.. 2009b. Must We Act Only On What We Know? Journal of Philosophy 106: 463–474.
Littlejohn, C. 2010. Moore's Paradox and Epistemic Norms. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88: 79–100.
Littlejohn, C. Forthcoming. Evidence and Armchair Access. Synthese.
Lynch, M. 2004. True to Life: Why Truth Matters. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Martin, M. G. F. 2002. The Transparency of Experience. Mind and Language 17(4): 376–425.
Martin, M. G. F. 2004. The Limits of Self-Awareness. Philosophical Studies 120(1–3): 37–89.
McDowell, J. 1982. Criteria, Defeasibility, and Knowledge. Proceedings of the British Academy 68: 455–479. Reprinted in McDowell, 1998.
McDowell, J.. 1994a. Knowledge by Hearsay. In Knowing from Words: Western and Indian Philosophical Analyses of Understanding and Testimony (ed. Matilal, B. K. and Chakrabarti, A.). Dordrecht: Kluwer, 195–224. Reprinted in McDowell, 1998.
McDowell, J. 1994b. Mind and World. Oxford University Press.
McDowell, J. 1998. Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Millar, A. 1991. Reasons and Experience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Millar, A. 2004. Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Millar, A.. 2007. What the Disjunctivist is Right About. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 176–198.
Millar, A.. 2008a. Disjunctivism and Skepticism. In The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (ed. Greco, J.). New York: Oxford University Press, 581–604.
Millar, A.. 2008b. Perceptual-Recognitional Abilities and Perceptual Knowledge. In Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge (ed. Haddock, A. and Macpherson, F. E.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 330–347.
Millar, A. 2009. What is it that Cognitive Abilities are Abilities to Do? Acta Analytica 24: 223–236.
Millar, A. 2010. Knowing from Being Told. In Social Epistemology (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D.). Oxford University Press, 175–193.
Mitova, V. 2009. A Quasi-Pragmatist Explanation of Our Ethics of Belief. Teorema 28(3): 113–130.
Moran, R. 2006. Getting Told and Being Believed. In The Epistemology of Testimony (ed. J. Lackey, and E. Sosa, ). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 272–306.
Moser, P. 1989. Knowledge and Evidence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Nagel, T. 1979. Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Oddie, G. 2005. Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford University Press.
Olson, J. 2009. Reasons and the New Non-Naturalism. In Spheres of Reason (ed. Robertson, S.). Oxford University Press, 164–182.
Olson, J.. 2010. In Defence of Moral Error Theory. In New Waves in Metaethics (ed. Brady, M.). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 62–84.
Owens, D. 2000. Reason Without Freedom. New York: Routledge.
Parfit, D. 2001. Reasons and Rationality. In Exploring Practical Rationality (ed. Egonsson, D., Josefsson, J., Petersson, B., and Rønnow-Rasmussen, T.). Aldershot: Ashgate, 17–39.
Peacocke, C. 2001. Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content? Journal of Philosophy 98: 239–264.
Peacocke, C.. 2004. The Realm of Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Percival, P. 2003. The Pursuit of Epistemic Good. Metaphilosophy 34: 29–47. Reprinted in Moral and Epistemic Virtues (ed. M. S. Brady and D. H. Pritchard). Oxford: Blackwell, 2003, 29–46.
Pollock, J. 1974. Knowledge and Justification. Princeton University Press.
Pollock, J.. 1986. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Pollock, J. and Cruz, J. 1999. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge, 2nd edition. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.
Price, H. H. 1932. Perception. London: Methuen.
Pritchard, D. H. 2007a. Knowledge, the Value of. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ed. Zalta, E.). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-value/
Pritchard, D. H.. 2007b. Recent Work on Epistemic Value. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44: 85–110.
Pritchard, D. H.. 2008. Greco on Knowledge: Virtues, Contexts, Achievements. Philosophical Quarterly 58: 437–447.
Pritchard, D. H.. 2009a. Knowledge, Understanding and Epistemic Value. In Epistemology (Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures) (ed. O'Hear, A.). Cambridge University Press, 19–44.
Pritchard, D. H.. 2009b. The Value of Knowledge. Harvard Review of Philosophy 16: 2–19.
Pritchard, D., Millar, A., and Haddock, A. 2010. The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations. OxfordUniversity Press.
Pryor, J. 2000. The Skeptic and the Dogmatist. Noûs 34: 517–549.
Pryor, J. 2004. What's Wrong with Moore's Argument? Philosophical Issues 14: 349–378.
Pryor, J.. 2005. There is Immediate Justification. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (ed. M. Steup, and E. Sosa, ). Oxford: Blackwell, 181–202.
Pryor, J.Forthcoming. When Warrant Transmits. In Wittgenstein, Epistemology and Mind: Themes from the Philosophy of Crispin Wright (ed. Coliva, A.). Oxford University Press.
Putnam, H. 1990. Beyond the Fact/Value Dichotomy. In Putnam, Realism with a Human Face (ed. Conant, J.). Cambridge University Press, 135–141.
Rabinowicz, W. and Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. 2004. The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Value. Ethics 114: 391–423.
Railton, P. 1997. On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action. In Ethics and Practical Reason (ed. Cullity, G. and Gaut, B.). Cambridge University Press, 53–80.
Raz, J. 1975. Practical Reason and Norms. London: Hutchinson.
Raz, J.. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Raz, J.. 1990. Practical Reason and Norms. New York: Oxford University Press.
Raz, J.. 1999. Engaging Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
Raz, J.. 2005. The Myth of Instrumental Rationality. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1(1): 2–28.
Reisner, A. 2004. Conflicts of Normativity. thesis, D. Phil, Oxford University.
Reisner, A. 2008. Weighing Pragmatic and Evidential Reasons for Belief. Philosophical Studies 138: 17–27.
Reisner, A.. 2009a. The Possibility of Pragmatic Reasons for Belief and the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem. Philosophical Studies 145(2): 257–272.
Reisner, A. 2009b. Unifying the Requirements of Rationality. Philosophical Explorations 12(3): 243–260.
Riggs, W. 2002a. Beyond Truth and Falsehood: The Real Value of Knowing that p. Philosophical Studies 107: 87–108.
Riggs, W.. 2002b. Reliability and the Value of Knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64: 79–96.
Riggs, W.. 2003. Understanding “Virtue” and the Virtue of Understanding. In Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (ed. Zagzebski, L. and DePaul, M.). Oxford University Press, 203–226.
Riggs, W.. 2007. The Value Turn in Epistemology. In New Waves in Epistemology (ed. Hendricks, V. and Pritchard, D. H.). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 300–323.
Riggs, W. 2009. Understanding, Knowledge, and the Meno Requirement. In Epistemic Value (ed. Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D. H.). Oxford University Press, 331–338.
Robinson, P. 1996. Competing Theories of Justification: Deeds v. Reasons. In Harm and Culpability (ed. Simester, A. and Smith, A.). New York: Oxford University Press, 45–70.
Scanlon, T.M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Schroeder, M. 2004. The Scope of Instrumental Reason. Philosophical Perspectives 18: 337–364.
Schroeder, M.. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford University Press.
Schroeder, M. 2008. Having Reasons. Philosophical Studies 139(1): 57–71.
Schroeder, M.. Forthcoming. Stakes, , Withholding, and the Subject-Sensitivity of Knowledge. Philosophical Studies.
Shah, N. 2003. How Truth Governs Belief. Philosophical Review 112: 447–483.
Shah, N.. 2006. A New Argument for Evidentialism. Philosophical Quarterly 56: 481–498.
Shah, N.. 2008. How Action Governs Intention. Philosophers' Imprint 8: 1–19.
Shah, N. and Velleman, D. 2005. Doxastic Deliberation. Philosophical Review 114: 497–534.
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.
Smith, M.. 2001. Some Not-Much-Discussed Problems for Non-Cognitivism in Ethics. Ratio 14(2): 93–115.
Sobel, D. and Wall, S. (eds.) 2009. Reasons for Action. Cambridge University Press.
Sobel, J. H. Good and Gold: A Judgmental History of Metaethics from G. E. Moore through J. L. Mackie (MS). www.utsc.utoronto.ca/∼sobel/Gd_Gld/
Sosa, E. 1988. Beyond Skepticism, to the Best of Our Knowledge. Mind 97: 153–189.
Sosa, E.. 1991. Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge University Press.
Sosa, E. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Volume I. Oxford University Press.
Speaks, J. 2005. Is There a Problem about Nonconceptual Content? Philosophical Review 114(3): 359–398.
Steglich-Petersen, A. 2006a. No Norm Needed: On the Aim of Belief. Philosophical Quarterly 56: 499–516.
Steglich-Petersen, A.. 2006b. Voluntarism and Transparent Deliberation. South African Journal of Philosophy 25: 171–176.
Steglich-Petersen, A.. 2008a. Against Essential Normativity of the Mental. Philosophical Studies 140: 263–283.
Steglich-Petersen, A.. 2008b. Does Doxastic Transparency Support Evidentialism? Dialectica 62: 541–547.
Steglich-Petersen, A.. 2009. Weighing the Aim of Belief. Philosophical Studies 145: 395–405.
Steup, M. 1999. A Defense of Internalism. In The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings (ed. Pojman, L.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 373–384.
Steup, M.. 2001. Epistemic Duty, Evidence, and Internality. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty (ed. Steup, M.). New York: Oxford University Press, 134–148.
Steup, M.. 2008. Doxastic Freedom. Synthese 161: 375–392.
Stich, S. 1990. The Fragmentation of Reason: Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stratton-Lake, P. 2002. Introduction. In D. Ross, The Right and the Good (ed. Stratton-Lake, P.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, ix–xlix.
Strawson, P. F. 1962. Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 1–25.
Strawson, P. F. 1979. Perception and Its Objects. In Perception and Identity: Essays presented to A. J. Ayer with His Replies to Them (ed. Macdonald, G. F.). London: Macmillan, 41–60.
Stroud, B. 2004. Perceptual Knowledge and Epistemological Satisfaction. In Ernest Sosa and His Critics (ed. Greco, J.). Oxford: Blackwell, 164–173.
Sutton, J. 2005. Stick to What You Know. Noûs 39: 359–396.
Sutton, J.. 2007. Without Justification. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sverdlik, S. 1996. Motive and Rightness. Ethics 106: 327–349.
Swinburne, R. 1999. Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford University Press.
Swinburne, R.. 2000. Epistemic Justification. Oxford University Press.
Textor, M. 2009. Are Particulars or States of Affairs Given in Perception? In States of Affairs (ed. Reicher, M.). Frankfurt/Main: Ontos, 129–150.
Travis, C. 2004. The Silence of the Senses. Mind 113: 57–94.
Travis, C. 2005. A Sense of Occasion. Philosophical Quarterly 55: 286–314.
Vahid, H. 2006. Aiming at Truth: Doxastic vs. Epistemic Goals. Philosophical Studies 131: 303–335.
Velleman, D. 2000. The Possibility of Practical Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wallace, J. 2001. Normativity, Commitment, and Instrumental Reason. Philosophers' Imprint 1: 1–26.
Wallace, R. J., Pettit, P., Scheffler, S., and Smith, M. (eds.) 2004. Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wedgwood, R. 1999. The A Priori Rules of Rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59: 113–131.
Wedgwood, R. 2002a. The Aim of Belief. Philosophical Perspectives 16: 267–297.
Wedgwood, R.. 2002b. Internalism Explained. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 349–369.
Wedgwood, R.. 2003. Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly. In Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality (ed. Stroud, S. and Tappolet, C.). Oxford University Press, 201–229.
Wedgwood, R.. 2007a. The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wedgwood, R.. 2007b. Normativism Defended. In Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind (ed. McLaughlin, B. and Cohen, J.). Oxford: Blackwell, 85–101.
Williams, B. 1973. Problems of the Self. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, B.. 1980. Internal and External Reasons. Reprinted in Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973–1980. Cambridge University Press, 1981, 101–113.
Williams, B.. 1995. Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame. In Making Sense of Humanity. Cambridge University Press, 35–45.
Williamson, T. 1995. Is Knowledge a State of Mind? Mind 104: 533–565.
Williamson, T.. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press.
Williamson, T.. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wright, C. 2001. On Basic Logical Knowledge. Philosophical Studies 106: 41–85.
Wright, C.. 2002. (Anti-)Sceptics Simple and Subtle: Moore and McDowell. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 330–348.
Wright, C.. 2003. Some Reflections on the Acquisition of Warrant by Inference. In New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge (ed. Nuccetelli, S.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 57–77.
Wright, C.. 2004. Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?Aristotelian Society Supplement 78: 167–212.
Wright, C.. 2007. The Perils of Dogmatism. In Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics (ed. Nuccetelli, S. and Seay, G.). Oxford University Press, 25–48.
Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.
Zagzebski, L.. 1999. What is Knowledge? In The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology (ed. Greco, J. and Sosa, E.). Oxford: Blackwell, 92–116.
Zagzebski, L. 2001. Recovering Understanding. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Virtue, and Responsibility (ed. Steup, M.). Oxford University Press, 235–252.
Zagzebski, L.. 2003. The Search for the Source of Epistemic Good. Metaphilosophy 34: 12–28. Reprinted in Moral and Epistemic Virtues (ed. M. S. Brady and D. H. Pritchard). Oxford: Blackwell, 13–28.
Zimmerman, M. 2002. Taking Luck Seriously. Journal of Philosophy 99: 553–576.

Metrics

Altmetric attention score

Full text views

Total number of HTML views: 0
Total number of PDF views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

Book summary page views

Total views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.