‘Poor Borelli!’ exclaimed Alexandre Koyre at the end
of his wonderful and by now classic
study of Borelli's ‘celestial mechanics’. Koyre frankly
admitted that Borelli lacked Newton's genius and intellectual audacity.
However, in his story Borelli deserved a place
between Kepler and Newton for his ‘imperfect but decisive’
unification of terrestrial and
celestial physics. This framework finds a powerful justification in Borelli's
extensive usage
of Keplerian astronomy and in Newton's references to Borelli's
work on the Medicean
planets, Theoricae mediceorum planetarum (Florence, 1666), both
in his correspondence
with Edmond Halley, with regard to a controversy with Robert Hooke, and
in
Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica (London, 1687). Newton's
own copy of
Borelli's work with signs of his reading – the famous
dog-earings – is preserved in the
library of Trinity College, Cambridge. The magnitude of Newton's achievement
has
haunted Borelli's work ever since Principia mathematica appeared
in print. For example,
although Christiaan Huygens was sent a copy of Borelli's book by Prince
Leopold in 1666,
his marginal annotations in his own copy of the book were written after
he had read
Newton's masterpiece, as if Huygens had felt the need to read the
book again after 1687.
From then onwards Borelli's work has almost inevitably appeared in
a new light that has
coloured its subsequent readings.
My ambition in this paper is to provide a fresh reading of Borelli's
work by
reconstructing its circumstances of composition, establishing a comparison
with a relevant
strictly contemporary source, and attending to the immediate reception
of Theoricae.
Borelli's work was written with an eye to a composite audience including
Roman Jesuits,
Sicilian intellectual circles and Leopold de' Medici's correspondents
across the Alps, such
as the Copernican astronomer Ismael Boulliau in Paris. Borelli was aware
that his Sicilian
readers were likely to have different concerns from those of Roman Jesuits
or the Medici.
Thus the task of charting the reception of his work is a formidable one.
For a variety of
reasons, including availability of sources, limitations of space, taste
and competence, my
analysis of Borelli's work on the Medicean planets is limited to a
few themes and is not only
no less partial than Koyre's, but in many respects it relies on it.
If readers feel stimulated
to re-read Koyre's text, one of the aims of this paper will have been
fulfilled.