No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Actual knowledge
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 19 November 2021
Abstract
This response argues that when you represent others as knowing something, you represent their mind as being related to the actual world. This feature of knowledge explains the limits of knowledge attribution, how knowledge differs from belief, and why knowledge underwrites learning from others. We hope this vision for how knowledge works spurs a new era in theory of mind research.
- Type
- Authors’ Response
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press
References
Apperly, I. A., Riggs, K. J., Simpson, A., Chiavarino, C., & Samson, D. (2006). Is belief reasoning automatic? Psychological Science, 17(10), 841–844.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baker, C. L., Jara-Ettinger, J., Saxe, R., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2017). Rational quantitative attribution of beliefs, desires and percepts in human mentalizing. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(4), 1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bricker, A. M. (2020). The neural and cognitive mechanisms of knowledge attribution: An EEG study. Cognition, 203, 104412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2020a). Knowledge and truth: A skeptical challenge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 101(1), 93–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2020b). Knowledge, adequacy, and approximate truth. Consciousness and Cognition, 83, 102950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S., & Machery, E. (2014). Epistemic intuitions in fake-barn thought experiments. Episteme; Rivista Critica di Storia Delle Scienze Mediche e Biologiche, 11(2), 199–212.Google Scholar
Dodell-Feder, D., Koster-Hale, J., Bedny, M., & Saxe, R. (2011). fMRI item analysis in a theory of mind task. Neuroimage, 55(2), 705–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dungan, J., & Saxe, R. (2012). Matched false-belief performance during verbal and nonverbal interference. Cognitive Science, 36, 1148–1156. doi: 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2012.01248.x.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe. Cognition, 109(2), 224–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koster-Hale, J., & Saxe, R. (2013). Theory of mind: A neural prediction problem. Neuron, 79(5), 836–848.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krachun, C., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). A competitive nonverbal false belief task for children and apes. Developmental Science, 12(4), 521–535.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771–785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, P. L., Koenig, M. A., Corriveau, K. H., & Jaswal, V. K. (2018). Cognitive foundations of learning from testimony. Annual Review of Psychology, 69, 251–273.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horschler, D. J., Santos, L. R., & MacLean, E. L. (2019). Do non-human primates really represent others’ ignorance? A test of the awareness relations hypothesis. Cognition, 190, 72–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horschler, D. J., Santos, L. R., & MacLean, E. L. (2021). How do non-human primates represent others’ awareness of where objects are hidden? Cognition, 212, 104658.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jara-Ettinger, J., Schulz, L. E., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2020). The naive utility calculus as a unified, quantitative framework for action understanding. Cognitive Psychology, 123, 101334.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kano, F., Krupenye, C., Hirata, S., Tomonaga, M., & Call, J. (2019). Great apes use self-experience to anticipate an agent's action in a false-belief test. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116, 20904–20909. doi: 201910095. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1910095116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovács, Á. M., Téglás, E., & Endress, A. D. (2010). The social sense: Susceptibility to others’ beliefs in human infants and adults. Science, 330(6012), 1830–1834.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krupenye, C., Kano, F., Hirata, S., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2016). Great apes anticipate that other individuals will act according to false beliefs. Science, 354(6308), 110–114, https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaf8110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of “theory of mind.” Psychological Review, 94(4), 412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., … Hashimoto, T. (2017). Gettier across cultures 1. Noûs, 51(3), 645–664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marticorena, D. C., Ruiz, A. M., Mukerji, C., Goddu, A., & Santos, L. R. (2011). Monkeys represent others’ knowledge but not their beliefs. Developmental Science, 14(6), 1406–1416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, S., Lonsdorf, E., Morgan, D., Prestipino, M., Bernstein-Kurtycz, L., Mundry, R., & Sanz, C. (2020). Teaching varies with task complexity in wild chimpanzees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(2), 969–976.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Myers-Schulz, B., & Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). Knowing that P without believing that P. Noûs, 47(2), 371–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, J., Knobe, J., Strickland, B., Armary, P., & Cushman, F. (2018). Evidence for evaluations of knowledge prior to belief. In Proceedings of the Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Phillips, J., Ong, D. C., Surtees, A. D., Xin, Y., Williams, S., Saxe, R., & Frank, M. C. (2015). A second look at automatic theory of mind: Reconsidering Kovács, Téglás, and Endress (2010). Psychological Science, 26(9), 1353–1367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(4), 515–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rapaport, L. G., & Brown, G. R. (2008). Social influences on foraging behavior in young nonhuman primates: Learning what, where, and how to eat. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 17(4), 189–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riggs, K. J., & Peterson, D. M. (2000). Counterfactual thinking in pre-school children: Mental state and causal inferences. In Mitchell, P. & Riggs, K. J. (Eds.), Children's reasoning and the mind, (pp. 87–99). Psychology Press/Taylor & Francis (UK).Google Scholar
Rose, D., Machery, E., Stich, S., Alai, M., Angelucci, A., Berniūnas, R., … Zhu, J. (2019). Nothing at stake in knowledge. Noûs, 53(1), 224–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saxe, R., & Kanwisher, N. (2003). People thinking about thinking people: The role of the temporo-parietal junction in “theory of mind.” Neuroimage, 19(4), 1835–1842.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shahaeian, A., Peterson, C. C., Slaughter, V., & Wellman, H. M. (2011). Culture and the sequence of steps in theory of mind development. Developmental Psychology, 47(5), 1239.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strickland, B. (2017). Language reflects “core” cognition: A new theory about the origin of cross-linguistic regularities. Cognitive Science, 41(1), 70–101.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turri, J. (2016a). A new paradigm for epistemology: From reliabilism to abilism. Ergo, 3(8), 189–231.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2016b). Knowledge and the norm of assertion: An essay in philosophical science. Open Book Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2018). Primate social cognition and the core human knowledge concept. In Mizumoto, M., Stich, S., & McCready, E. (Eds.), Epistemology for the rest of the world: Linguistic and cultural diversity and epistemology, (pp. 279–290). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wellman, H. M., & Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. Child Development, 75(2), 523–541.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williamson, T. (2002). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press on Demand.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yuan, Y., & Kim, M. (forthcoming). Cross-Cultural universality of knowledge attributions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology.Google Scholar
Target article
Knowledge before belief
Related commentaries (36)
Are knowledge- and belief-reasoning automatic, and is this the right question?
Belief versus knowledge: An epic battle, but no clear victor
Beliefs for human-unique social learning
Beyond knowledge versus belief: The contents of mental-state representations and their underlying computations
Do knowledge representations facilitate learning under epistemic uncertainty?
Do “knowledge attributions” involve metarepresentation just like belief attributions do?
Evolutionary foundations of knowledge and belief attribution in nonhuman primates
Exchanging humpty dumpties is not a solution: Why a representational view of knowledge must be replaced with an action-based approach
Ignorance matters
Infants actively seek and transmit knowledge via communication
Insights into the uniquely human origins of understanding other minds
Intersubjectivity and social learning: Representation of beliefs enables the accumulation of cultural knowledge
Knowing, believing, and acting as if you know
Knowledge is belief – and shaped by culture
Knowledge and the brain: Why the knowledge-centric theory of mind program needs neuroscience
Knowledge as commitment
Knowledge before belief in the history of philosophy
Knowledge before belief: Evidence from unconscious content
Knowledge by default
Knowledge prior to belief: Is extended better than enacted?
Knowledge, belief, and moral psychology
Knowledge-by-acquaintance before propositional knowledge/belief
No way around cross-cultural and cross-linguistic epistemology
Relational mentalizing after any representation
Representation and misrepresentation of knowledge
Representing knowledge, belief, and everything in between: Representational complexity in humans and other apes
Semantic memory before episodic memory: How memory research can inform knowledge and belief representations
Teleology first: Goals before knowledge and belief
The distinctive character of knowledge
The evolution of knowledge during the Cambrian explosion
The role of epistemic emotions in learning from others
Theory of mind in context: Mental-state representations for social evaluation
There's more to consider than knowledge and belief
Three cognitive mechanisms for knowledge tracking
Two distinct concepts of knowledge
Why is knowledge faster than (true) belief?
Author response
Actual knowledge