No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Ignorance matters
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 19 November 2021
Abstract
The ability to reason about ignorance is an important and often overlooked representational capacity. Phillips and colleagues assume that knowledge representations are inevitably accompanied by ignorance representations. We argue that this is not necessarily the case, as agents who can reason about knowledge often fail on ignorance tasks, suggesting that ignorance should be studied as a separate representational capacity.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press
References
Birch, S. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). Children are cursed: An asymmetric bias in mental-state attribution. Psychological Science, 14(3), 283–286.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Call, J., & Carpenter, M. (2001). Do apes and children know what they have seen? Animal Cognition, 3(4), 207–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drayton, L. A., & Santos, L. R. (2018). What do monkeys know about others’ knowledge? Cognition, 170, 201–208.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Feiman, R., Mody, S., Sanborn, S., & Carey, S. (2017). What do you mean, no? Toddlers’ comprehension of logical “no” and “not.” Language Learning and Development, 13(4), 430–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flombaum, J. I., & Santos, L. R. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology, 15(5), 447–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, O., & Petrashek, A. R. (2009). Children do not follow the rule “ignorance means getting it wrong.” Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 102(1), 114–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, K. J., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J., Goodman, N., & Baker, C. (2013). The mentalistic basis of core social cognition: Experiments in preverbal infants and a computational model. Developmental Science, 16(2), 209–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771–785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogrefe, G. J., Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1986). Ignorance versus false belief: A developmental lag in attribution of epistemic states. Child Development, 57(3), 567–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horschler, D. J., Santos, L. R., & MacLean, E. L. (2019). Do non-human primates really represent others’ ignorance? A test of the awareness relations hypothesis. Cognition, 190, 72–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huang, Z., Hu, Q., & Shao, Y. (2019). Understanding others’ knowledge certainty from inference and information-seeking behaviors in children. Developmental Psychology, 55(7), 1372.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Karg, K., Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2015a). The goggles experiment: Can chimpanzees use self-experience to infer what a competitor can see? Animal Behaviour, 105, 211–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karg, K., Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2015b). Chimpanzees strategically manipulate what others can see. Animal Cognition, 18(5), 1069–1076.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koenig, M. A., & Echols, C. H. (2003). Infants’ understanding of false labeling events: The referential roles of words and the speakers who use them. Cognition, 87(3), 179–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luo, Y., & Johnson, S. C. (2009). Recognizing the role of perception in action at 6 months. Developmental Science, 12(1), 142–149.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marticorena, D. C., Ruiz, A. M., Mukerji, C., Goddu, A., & Santos, L. R. (2011). Monkeys represent others’ knowledge but not their beliefs. Developmental Science, 14(6), 1406–1416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, A., & Santos, L. R. (2016). What cognitive representations support primate theory of mind? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(5), 375–382.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mody, S., & Carey, S. (2016). The emergence of reasoning by the disjunctive syllogism in early childhood. Cognition, 154, 40–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mossler, D. G., Marvin, R. S., & Greenberg, M. T. (1976). Conceptual perspective taking in 2-to 6-year-old children. Developmental Psychology, 12(1), 85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nordmeyer, A. E., & Frank, M. C. (2014). The role of context in young children's comprehension of negation. Journal of Memory and Language, 77, 25–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, D. K. (1996). Two-year-old children's sensitivity to a parent's knowledge state when making requests. Child Development, 67(2), 659–677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reuter, T., Feiman, R., & Snedeker, J. (2018). Getting to no: Pragmatic and semantic factors in two- and three-year-olds’ understanding of negation. Child Development, 89(4), e364–e381.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ruffman, T. (1996). Do children understand the mind by means of simulation or a theory? Evidence from their understanding of inference. Mind & Language, 11(4), 388–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, K., & Winner, E. (1991). When 3-year-olds understand ignorance, false belief and representational change. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9(1), 159–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wellman, H. M., & Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. Child Development, 75(2), 523–541.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Target article
Knowledge before belief
Related commentaries (36)
Are knowledge- and belief-reasoning automatic, and is this the right question?
Belief versus knowledge: An epic battle, but no clear victor
Beliefs for human-unique social learning
Beyond knowledge versus belief: The contents of mental-state representations and their underlying computations
Do knowledge representations facilitate learning under epistemic uncertainty?
Do “knowledge attributions” involve metarepresentation just like belief attributions do?
Evolutionary foundations of knowledge and belief attribution in nonhuman primates
Exchanging humpty dumpties is not a solution: Why a representational view of knowledge must be replaced with an action-based approach
Ignorance matters
Infants actively seek and transmit knowledge via communication
Insights into the uniquely human origins of understanding other minds
Intersubjectivity and social learning: Representation of beliefs enables the accumulation of cultural knowledge
Knowing, believing, and acting as if you know
Knowledge is belief – and shaped by culture
Knowledge and the brain: Why the knowledge-centric theory of mind program needs neuroscience
Knowledge as commitment
Knowledge before belief in the history of philosophy
Knowledge before belief: Evidence from unconscious content
Knowledge by default
Knowledge prior to belief: Is extended better than enacted?
Knowledge, belief, and moral psychology
Knowledge-by-acquaintance before propositional knowledge/belief
No way around cross-cultural and cross-linguistic epistemology
Relational mentalizing after any representation
Representation and misrepresentation of knowledge
Representing knowledge, belief, and everything in between: Representational complexity in humans and other apes
Semantic memory before episodic memory: How memory research can inform knowledge and belief representations
Teleology first: Goals before knowledge and belief
The distinctive character of knowledge
The evolution of knowledge during the Cambrian explosion
The role of epistemic emotions in learning from others
Theory of mind in context: Mental-state representations for social evaluation
There's more to consider than knowledge and belief
Three cognitive mechanisms for knowledge tracking
Two distinct concepts of knowledge
Why is knowledge faster than (true) belief?
Author response
Actual knowledge