No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Beliefs for human-unique social learning
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 19 November 2021
Abstract
Phillips et al. argue that understanding what others know is central to social cognition across species and that this understanding underlies human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge. Knowledge representations can't be both what we have in common with our evolutionary ancestors and what sets us apart from them. Belief representations are necessary for human-unique social learning.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press
References
Astington, J. W., & Jenkins, J. M. (1995). Theory of mind development and social understanding. Cognition & Emotion, 9(2–3), 151–165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Astington, J. W., & Pelletier, J. (2005). Theory of mind, language, and learning in the early years: Developmental origins of school readiness. In Homer, B. D. & Tamis-Lemonda, C. (Eds.), The development of social cognition and communication (pp. 205–230). Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Bartsch, K., London, K., & Campbell, M. D. (2007). Children's attention to beliefs in interactive persuasion tasks. Developmental Psychology, 43(1), 111.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bass, I., Gopnik, A., Hanson, M., Ramarajan, D., Shafto, P., Wellman, H., & Bonawitz, E. (2019). Children's developing theory of mind and pedagogical evidence selection. Developmental Psychology, 55(2), 286.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blair, C., & Razza, R. P. (2007). Relating effortful control, executive function, and false belief understanding to emerging math and literacy ability in kindergarten. Child Development, 78(2), 647–663.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brosseau-Liard, P., Penney, D., & Poulin-Dubois, D. (2015). Theory of mind selectively predicts preschoolers’ knowledge-based selective word learning. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 33(4), 464–475.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grueneisen, S., Wyman, E., & Tomasello, M. (2015). “I know you don't know I know…” Children use second-order false-belief reasoning for peer coordination. Child Development, 86(1), 287–293.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harris, P. L., & Corriveau, K. H. (2011). Young children's selective trust in informants. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366(1567), 1179–1187.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harris, P. L., Corriveau, K. H., Pasquini, E. S., Koenig, M., Fusaro, M., & Clément, F. (2012). Credulity and the development of selective trust in early childhood. In Beran, M., Brandl, J. L., Perner, J., & Proust, J. (Eds.), Foundations of metacognition (pp. 193–210). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyes, C. (2018). Cognitive gadgets: The cultural evolution of thinking. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, C. C., Slaughter, V., & Wellman, H. M. (2018). Nimble negotiators: How theory of mind (ToM) interconnects with persuasion skills in children with and without ToM delay. Developmental Psychology, 54(3), 494.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peterson, C. C., & Wellman, H. M. (2019). Longitudinal theory of mind (ToM) development from preschool to adolescence with and without ToM delay. Child Development, 90(6), 1917–1934.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Poulin-Dubois, D., Rakoczy, H., Burnside, K., Crivello, C., Dörrenberg, S., Edwards, K., … Low, J. (2018). Do infants understand false beliefs? We don't know yet – A commentary on Baillargeon, Buttelmann and Southgate's commentary. Cognitive Development, 48, 302–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, H., Koster-Hale, J., Caselli, N., Magid, R., Benedict, R., Olson, H., … Saxe, R. (2020). Reduced neural selectivity for mental states in deaf children with delayed exposure to sign language. Nature Communications, 11(1), 1–13.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richardson, H., Lisandrelli, G., Riobueno-Naylor, A., & Saxe, R. (2018). Development of the social brain from age three to twelve years. Nature Communications, 9(1), 1027.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slaughter, V., Peterson, C. C., & Moore, C. (2013). I can talk you into it: Theory of mind and persuasion behavior in young children. Developmental Psychology, 49(2), 227.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weinstein, E. A. (1969). The development of interpersonal competence. In Goslin, D. A. (Ed.), Handbook of socialization theory and research (pp. 753–775). Rand McNally.Google Scholar
Wellman, H. M., Fang, F., & Peterson, C. C. (2011). Sequential progressions in a theory-of-mind scale: Longitudinal perspectives. Child Development, 82(3), 780–792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zigler, E., & Trickett, P. K. (1978). IQ, social competence, and evaluation of early childhood intervention programs. American Psychologist, 33(9), 789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ziv, M., & Frye, D. (2004). Children's understanding of teaching: The role of knowledge and belief. Cognitive Development, 19(4), 457–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Target article
Knowledge before belief
Related commentaries (36)
Are knowledge- and belief-reasoning automatic, and is this the right question?
Belief versus knowledge: An epic battle, but no clear victor
Beliefs for human-unique social learning
Beyond knowledge versus belief: The contents of mental-state representations and their underlying computations
Do knowledge representations facilitate learning under epistemic uncertainty?
Do “knowledge attributions” involve metarepresentation just like belief attributions do?
Evolutionary foundations of knowledge and belief attribution in nonhuman primates
Exchanging humpty dumpties is not a solution: Why a representational view of knowledge must be replaced with an action-based approach
Ignorance matters
Infants actively seek and transmit knowledge via communication
Insights into the uniquely human origins of understanding other minds
Intersubjectivity and social learning: Representation of beliefs enables the accumulation of cultural knowledge
Knowing, believing, and acting as if you know
Knowledge is belief – and shaped by culture
Knowledge and the brain: Why the knowledge-centric theory of mind program needs neuroscience
Knowledge as commitment
Knowledge before belief in the history of philosophy
Knowledge before belief: Evidence from unconscious content
Knowledge by default
Knowledge prior to belief: Is extended better than enacted?
Knowledge, belief, and moral psychology
Knowledge-by-acquaintance before propositional knowledge/belief
No way around cross-cultural and cross-linguistic epistemology
Relational mentalizing after any representation
Representation and misrepresentation of knowledge
Representing knowledge, belief, and everything in between: Representational complexity in humans and other apes
Semantic memory before episodic memory: How memory research can inform knowledge and belief representations
Teleology first: Goals before knowledge and belief
The distinctive character of knowledge
The evolution of knowledge during the Cambrian explosion
The role of epistemic emotions in learning from others
Theory of mind in context: Mental-state representations for social evaluation
There's more to consider than knowledge and belief
Three cognitive mechanisms for knowledge tracking
Two distinct concepts of knowledge
Why is knowledge faster than (true) belief?
Author response
Actual knowledge