Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T16:49:50.820Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Representing knowledge, belief, and everything in between: Representational complexity in humans and other apes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 November 2021

Kresimir Durdevic
Affiliation:
School of Psychology & Neuroscience, University of St Andrews, St AndrewsKY16 9JP, UKkd96@st-andrews.ac.uk
Christopher Krupenye
Affiliation:
Department of Psychological & Brain Sciences, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD21218krupenye@jhu.eduhttp://christopherkrupenye.weebly.com/ Department of Psychology, Durham University, DurhamDH1 3LE, UK.

Abstract

Building on Phillips and colleagues' case for the primacy of knowledge, we advocate for attention to diversity in mentalizing constructs within, as well as between, knowledge and belief. Ultimately, as great apes and other animals show, the development and evolution of theory of mind may reflect a much greater range of incremental elaborations of representational or computational complexity.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buttelmann, D., Buttelmann, F., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2017). Great apes distinguish true from false beliefs in an interactive helping task. PLOS ONE, 12(4), e0173793. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0173793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (1999). A nonverbal false belief task: The performance of children and great apes. Child Development, 70(2), 381395. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8624.00028.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121123. JSTOR. https://doi.org/10.2307/3326922.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Chimpanzees deceive a human competitor by hiding. Cognition, 101(3), 495514. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2005.01.011.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horschler, D. J., Santos, L. R., & MacLean, E. L. (2019). Do non-human primates really represent others’ ignorance? A test of the awareness relations hypothesis. Cognition, 190, 7280. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2019.04.012.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe. Cognition, 109(2), 224234. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2008.08.010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kano, F., Krupenye, C., Hirata, S., Tomonaga, M., & Call, J. (2019). Great apes use self-experience to anticipate an agent's action in a false-belief test. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(42), 2090420909. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1910095116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karg, K., Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2015). Chimpanzees strategically manipulate what others can see. Animal Cognition, 18(5), 10691076. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-015-0875-z.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krachun, C., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). A competitive nonverbal false belief task for children and apes. Developmental Science, 12(4), 521535. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-7687.2008.00793.x.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krupenye, C. (2020). The evolution of mentalizing in humans and other primates. In Gilead, M. & Ochsner, K. (Eds.), The neural basis of mentalizing: A social-cognitive and affective neuroscience perspective (pp. 107–129). Springer Press. doi: 10.1007/978-3-030-51890-5.Google Scholar
Krupenye, C., Kano, F., Hirata, S., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2016). Great apes anticipate that other individuals will act according to false beliefs. Science, 354(6308), 110114. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaf8110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martin, A., & Santos, L. R. (2016). What cognitive representations support primate theory of mind? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(5), 375382. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.005.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nagel, J. (2017). Factive and nonfactive mental state attribution. Mind & Language, 32(5), 525544. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perner, J., Huemer, M., & Leahy, B. (2015). Mental files and belief: A cognitive theory of how children represent belief and its intensionality. Cognition, 145, 7788. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2015.08.006.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Phillips, J., & Norby, A. (2021). Factive theory of mind. Mind & Language, 36, 3–26. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rakoczy, H., Bergfeld, D., Schwarz, I., & Fizke, E. (2015). Explicit theory of mind is even more unified than previously assumed: Belief ascription and understanding aspectuality emerge together in development. Child Development, 86(2), 486502. https://doi.org/10.1111/cdev.12311.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed