Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T15:53:38.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What is exactly the problem with panpsychism?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2022

Cyriel M. A. Pennartz*
Affiliation:
Department of Cognitive and Systems Neuroscience, Faculty of Science, University of Amsterdam, 1098 XHAmsterdam, The Netherlands. c.m.a.pennartz@uva.nl; sils.uva.nl/content/research-groups/cognitive-and-systems-neuroscience/cognitive-and-systems-neuroscience.html?cb

Abstract

Merker et al.'s critique calls for a deeper analysis of panpsychism. In principle, the concept of integrated information can be applied to photodiodes and subatomic particles, but I suggest the main obstacle is the lack of any evidence to confirm the presence of consciousness. Also MRW's perspectivalist theory illustrates the difficulties in synthesizing a full-fledged theory of consciousness.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bayne, T. (2018). On the axiomatic foundations of the integrated information theory of consciousness. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2018(1), niy007. doi:10.1093/nc/niy007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
FitzGerald, T. H. B., Dolan, R. J., & Friston, K. (2015). Dopamine, reward learning, and active inference. Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience, 9(136), 116. doi:10.3389/fncom.2015.00136CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pennartz, C. M. A. (2009). Identification and integration of sensory modalities: Neural basis and relation to consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(3), 718739. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2009.03.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pennartz, C. M. A. (2015). The brain's representational power – On consciousness and the integration of modalities. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennartz, C. M. A., Farisco, M., & Evers, K. (2019). Indicators and criteria of consciousness in animals and intelligent machines: An inside-out approach. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 13, 25. doi:10.3389/fnsys.2019.00025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rao, R. P., & Ballard, D. H. (1999). Predictive coding in the visual cortex: A functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nature Neuroscience, 2(1), 7987. doi:10.1038/4580CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Searle, J. R. (2013). Can information theory explain consciousness? New York Review of Books, 5458.Google Scholar
Spratling, M. W. (2017). A review of predictive coding algorithms. Brain and Cognition, 112, 9297. doi:10.1016/j.bandc.2015.11.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tononi, G. (2015). Integrated information theory. Scholarpedia, 10(1), 4164. doi:http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Integrated_information_theoryCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., & Koch, C. (2016). Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17(7), 450461. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.44CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tononi, G., & Koch, C. (2015). Consciousness: Here, there and everywhere? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 370(1668), 118. doi:10.1098/rstb.2014.0167CrossRefGoogle Scholar