Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T05:03:26.141Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why evolve consciousness? Neural credit and blame allocation as a core function of consciousness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2022

W. Tecumseh Fitch*
Affiliation:
Department of Behavioral and Cognitive Biology, Faculty of Life Sciences, University of Vienna, Vienna1030, Austria. Tecumseh.fitch@uniie.ac.at

Abstract

I concur with Merker and colleague's critiques, suggesting that hypotheses about the evolutionary function of consciousness can help address them. Brains are parallel systems that function to compute possible actions and predict outcomes. I hypothesize that a core function of consciousness per se is the global feedback of information about those actions actually executed, supporting local learning via neuronal updating.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Birch, J., Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2020). Unlimited associative learning and the origins of consciousness: A primer and some predictions. Biology and Philosophy, 35(56), 123. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09772-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crick, F. C., & Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences, 2, 263275.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown & Co.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C., & Kinsbourne, M. (1995). Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, T. E, & Mallatt, J. M. (2016). The ancient origins of consciousness: How the brain created experience. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitch, W. T. (2005). Computation and cognition: Four distinctions and their implications. In Cutler, A. (Ed.), Twenty-First century psycholinguistics: Four cornerstones (pp. 381400). Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Fitch, W. T. (2008). Nano-intentionality: A defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biology and Philosophy, 23(2), 157177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humphrey, N. K. (2006). Seeing red: A study in consciousness. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. (1890). Principles of psychology. Henry Holt.Google Scholar
Merker, B. (2007). Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 30(1), 6381.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Merker, B. (2012). From probabilities to percepts: A subcortical “global best estimate buffer” as locus of phenomenal experience. In Edelman, S., Fekete, T. & Zach, N. (Eds.), Being in time. Dynamical models of phenomenal experience (pp. 3779): John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reber, A. S. (2018). The first minds: Caterpillars, karyotes and consciousness: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar